This pamphlet is now available online here.
In order to know whether the communist revolution is necessary and possible today, we have to pose the question of the decadence of capitalism, to define the historic basis of the programme and strategy of the proletariat in the present epoch.
Questions such as the content of socialism, the nature of the unions, the politics of ‘frontism’, the nature of national liberation movements, are intimately linked to an analysis of the decadence of capitalism.
It is not because the immense majority of men are exploited and thus alienated that socialism is a historic necessity today. Exploitation and alienation already existed under slavery, feudalism, and nineteenth century capitalism, but socialism could not possibly have been realised in any of those epochs.
For socialism to become a reality not only must the means for its instigation (the working class and the means of production) be sufficiently developed, but also the system which it is to supersede - capitalism - must have ceased to be a system indispensable to the development of the productive forces, must have become a growing fetter on the productive forces, that is to say, that it must have entered its period of decline or decadence.
The socialists of the early nineteenth century regarded socialism as an ideal to be attained, and its realisation was to result from the sheer good will of men - in the case of the ‘utopian’ socialists, from the good will of the ruling class itself. The enduring contribution of Marx and Engels was their understanding and scientific elaboration of the material necessity for the disappearance of capitalism and the realisation of communism. It is no accident that when Marx attempted to encapsulate the essence of his work in a single passage, he concentrated on the mechanisms of the historic growth and decay of the various modes of production through which humanity has developed:
“In the social production of their life, men enter into definite relations that are indispensable and independent of their will, relations of production which correspond to a definite stage of development of their material productive forces. The sum total of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the social, political and intellectual life process in general. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their being, but, on the contrary, their social being that determines their consciousness. At a certain stage of their development, the material productive forces of society come in conflict with the existing relations of production, or - what is but a legal expression of the same thing - with the property relations within which they have been at work hitherto. From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. Then begins an epoch of social revolution. With the change of the economic foundation the entire immense superstructure is more or less rapidly transformed. In considering such transformations a distinction should always be made between the material transformation of the economic conditions of production, which can be determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal, political, religious, aesthetic or philosophic - in short ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out. Just as our opinion of an individual is not based on what he thinks of himself, so we cannot judge such a period of transformation by its own consciousness; on the contrary, this consciousness must be explained rather from the contradictions of material life, from the existing conflict between the social productive forces and the relations of production. No social order ever perishes before all the productive forces for which there is room in it have developed; and new, higher relations of production never appear before the material conditions of their existence hove matured in the womb of the old society itself. Therefore mankind always sets itself only such tasks as it can solve; since, looking at the matter more closely, it will always be found that the task itself only arises when the material conditions for its solution already exist or are at least in the process of formation. In broad outlines Asiatic, ancient, feudal and modern bourgeois modes of production can be designated as progressive epochs in the economic formation of society.” (Marx, Preface to a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy)
The methodological approach adopted in this passage remains indispensable for understanding how different societies arise and decline. The appreciation that a mode of production cannot expire until the relations of production upon which that social system is based have become fetters on the further development of the productive forces is the basis for the definition of the proletariat’s political programme. Marx and Engels were quite clear that the perspective for the communist revolution was bound up with the global and historic evolution of capitalism itself.
What was less clear for Marx, especially in his earlier writings, was the actual delineation of the “epoch of social revolution” in capitalism’s development; and this lack of clarity was itself an objective product of the fact that the methodology of historical materialism emerged long before that epoch had dawned: Marx issued his first clarion calls to the proletarian revolution not in the period of capitalism’s decline, but of its most spectacular ascent. The imminent proletarian revolution proclaimed in the Communist Manifesto was thrust aside by the continued growth and expansion of capitalist social relations across the whole planet. Marx was definitely wrong to assert at that time that capitalist social relations had entered into a final conflict with the productive forces; although the collision between the two was always a feature of capitalism, the conflict was never irrevocable in the nineteenth century because capital still had vast areas of the globe available for its continued enlarged reproduction, for offsetting the fundamental contradictions which Marx had identified in its process of accumulation: the tendency towards generalised overproduction and the saturation of the market, and the tendency for the rate of profit to decline.
Despite these errors, however, Marx and Engels were still able to base their programme on the recognition that capitalism had yet to exhaust its progressive mission. This recognition was expressed for example in those passages in the Manifesto which talk about the tasks of the proletariat if it were to come to power at that time: the measures advocated are aimed at developing capitalism in the most progressive possible manner, rather than at destroying it root and branch (and thus what was a good example of Marx’s insight has unfortunately been turned into a reactionary state capitalist programme by those who advocate the same measures in the present epoch). More important, the practice of the marxists in the First International was correctly based on the understanding that since capitalism still had a progressive role to play, it was necessary for the working class to support those bourgeois movements which were helping to lay the historic groundwork for socialism (for example the struggles for national unification in Italy, Germany and the USA); similarly, that it was necessary for the workers to continue to fight for reforms since the growth of capitalism made reforms possible, and since the struggle for reforms enabled the workers to constitute themselves into a cohesive and social and political force. These materialist positions were defended against the anarchists’ a-historical demands for the immediate abolition of capitalism and their complete opposition to the struggle for reforms (these positions, though apparently ultra-revolutionary, actually concealed a petty bourgeois desire to ‘abolish’ capitalism and wage labour not by advancing towards their historical supercession but by regressing to the world of the independent small producer).
The Second International made the strategic adaptation to the epoch even more explicitly by elaborating a ‘minimum programme’ of immediately obtainable reforms (trade union recognition, shortening of the working day, etc) alongside a ‘maximum programme’ of socialism to be put into practice when the inevitable historic crisis of capitalism came about.
But for the majority of the chief tacticians and official leaders of the Second International the minimum programme was to become more and more the only real programme of the social democratic parties. Socialism, proletarian revolution, became mere sermonising platitudes to be trotted out on May Day parades, while the energy of the official movement was more and more focussed upon winning a place for social democracy within the capitalist system. Inevitably the ‘revisionist’ wing of the International (Bernstein etc) began to reject the very idea of the necessity for the collapse of capitalism and thus for a revolutionary transition to socialism, and to argue for the possibility of a gradual and peaceful transformation of capitalism into socialism.
These ideologies were nurtured by the extraordinary development of the world capitalist economy in the last part of the 19th century, but this was already the last stage in the ascendant march of the capitalist system: imperialist expansion was beginning to show itself as the precursor to a new and catastrophic phase in the life of bourgeois society, and class antagonisms were becoming increasingly sharp and widespread (mass strikes in America, Germany, and above all Russia). Against the opportunist theorising of Bernstein and co, and the temporising of the social democratic ‘centre’ (Kautsky etc), the left wing within the International - Luxemburg, the Bolsheviks, the Dutch Tribune group etc - defended the fundamental marxist dictum of the necessity for the eventual violent overthrow of capitalism. The clearest statement of this defence was Luxemburg’s Social Reform or Revolution (1898) which, while recognising that capitalism was still ascending by means of “brusque expansionist thrusts” (i.e. imperialism), insisted that the system would inevitably undergo a saturation of the world market, impelling its “crisis of senility” and producing an immediate need for the revolutionary conquest of power by the proletariat. In 1913 Luxemburg published her great theoretical work The Accumulation of Capital, which attempted to analyse the real economic roots of this historic crisis, whose actual arrival was shortly to be announced to humanity in the form of the first imperialist world war.
Basing herself on Marx’s own insistence that the very nature of the wage labour relationship made it impossible for capitalism to realise all the surplus value it extracted within its own social boundaries, Luxemburg concluded that capitalism’s historic decline must commence at the point where there is an exhaustion of the extra-capitalist markets in relation to the amount of surplus value generated by global capitalist production; for Luxemburg, capitalism was “...the first mode of economy which is unable to exist by itself, which needs other economic systems as a medium and a soil. Although it strives to become universal, and indeed on account of this tendency, it must break down – because it is immanently incapable of becoming a universal form of production.” (Accumulation of Capital). In sum, at the point which it dominated the globe, capitalism plunged into a permanent crisis of overproduction.
This conclusion remains to this day the clearest statement about the fundamental origins of the decadence of capitalism, subject of course to the various theoretical elaborations which the experience of another eighty years of decadence has enabled the revolutionary movement to put forward.
The outbreak of imperialist war in 1914 marked a historic turning point both in the history of capitalism and in the workers’ movement. No longer was the problem of the “crisis of senility” a theoretical debate between different wings of the workers’ movement. The understanding that the war marked a new period for capitalism as an historical system required and enabled the genuine marxist currents to draw a class frontier between themselves and those who, in one way or another, became apologists for the imperialist war. It was no accident that the frontier was essentially drown up between the old opportunist wing of social democracy - now openly acting as recruiting sergeants of the bourgeoisie - and the left fractions who had previously held on to the ground principles of the marxist theory of crisis. Luxemburg’s Internationale group, Lenin’s Bolshevik fraction, the left radicals of Bremen - these and others were the ones who held aloft the principles of proletarian internationalism, affirming that the war demonstrated the opening up of that period of “wars and revolutions” predicted by Marx, and calling for the proletariat to oppose the imperialist war with its own revolutionary combat.
Of the revolutionaries who gathered together at the conferences of the internationalist opposition at Zimmerwald and Kienthal, the clearest on the question of the war itself were the Bolsheviks, who together with the German radicals insisted on the slogan “turn the imperialist war into a civil war”, sharply delineating the revolutionary position on the war from that of various centrist and semi-pacifist currents. And as the revolutionary situation in Russia matured, the Bolsheviks’ (and above all Lenin’s) understanding of the tasks of the new period enabled them to attack the mechanistic and nationalistic sophistries of the Mensheviks; while the latter attempted to hold back the tide of revolution by arguing that Russia was ‘too backward’ for socialism, the Bolsheviks pointed out that the world-imperialist nature of the war indicated the ripeness of the world capitalist system for socialist revolution. They thus boldly argued for the seizure of power by the Russian working class as a prelude to the world proletarian revolution.
It was to further the interests of the world revolution that the Bolsheviks were instrumental in the foundation of the Communist International in 1919. The revolutionary parties which rallied round the banner of the Third International were fully aware of the crucial importance of defining the historic period for the elaboration of the communist programme:
“Aims and Tactics
1. The present epoch is the epoch of the disintegration and collapse of the entire capitalist wodd system, which will drag the whole of European civilisation down with it if capitalism with its insoluble contradictions is not destroyed.
2. The task of the proletariat is now to seize the State power immediately. The seizure of State power means the destruction of the State apparatus of the bourgeoisie and the organisation of a new proletarian apparatus of power.”
(From the ‘Invitation to the First Congress of the Communist International’, January 24, 1919)
The proclamations of the First Congress of the CI show a resounding clarity and confidence about the revolutionary tasks of the working class. Their whole emphasis was on the necessity for the immediate conquest of power by the workers, based on the dictatorship of the workers’ councils. There is consequently a clear understanding about the necessity for a break with the old aims and organisations of the pre-war workers’ movement: the social democratic parties which had supported the war effort and then done all they could to crush the post-war revolutionary movements were roundly denounced as agents of capitalism, and cooperation with these organs was rejected; parliamentarism was to a great extent seen as being incapable of serving the interests of the working class; the problem of colonial oppression could, it was stated, only be solved in the context of a world socialist society. These and other positions reflected the ascendant tide of revolution which was then sweeping through the whole world.
But the following congresses of the International, and especially the Third, in 1921, showed a marked deterioration in coherence and revolutionary principles, and this is turn reflected the reflux of the world revolution and the advancing degeneration of the Bolshevik party in the context of the isolation of the Russian Soviet State. As the latter more and more took on the task of managing Russian national capital, and as the Bolshevik party became more and more inextricably fused with the state, the International itself began to function more as an instrument of Russian foreign policy than as the world party of the revolution. The desperate attempts of the Bolsheviks to salvage something from this counter-revolutionary momentum led them to abandon the sharp revolutionary positions of the First Congress and to drift back towards the obsolete tactics of the previous period: parliamentarism, trade unionism, united fronts with the social democratic parties, support for the national liberation struggle in the colonies, and so on. That all these tactics were justified by a revolutionary verbiage could not alter the fact that the change in the historic period could only render such tactics directly counter-revolutionary, no matter what were the intentions of those who resorted to them.
Those who today act within the working class as the extreme left wing of capitalism - Stalinists, Trotskyists, etc - are indeed the true inheritors of these counter-revolutionary policies; what were once the mistakes of the workers’ movement have become the raison d’etre of these bourgeois gangs. Of course Stalinist and Trotskyists may pay lip service to various concepts of capitalist decadence, but this is robbed of any material basis as soon as one considers that throughout their history these currents have considered a large part of the world to be ‘socialist’ or at least ‘non-capitalist’, and therefore historically ascendant and deserving the support of ‘revolutionaries’; even those leftists who consider the Stalinist regimes to be state capitalist have never hesitated to support either them or various third world countries in the innumerable inter-imperialist wars that have ravaged the planet since World War Two. In any case the application of the theory of capitalist decay to the countries these leftists do consider to be capitalist is entirely subordinated to their immediate pragmatic needs as apologists for capital: no amount of talk about state capitalism by the British Socialist Workers Party, for example, has ever prevented it from seeing something progressive in nationalisation and something working class in the Labour or Communist Parties.
At the time of the first great revolutionary wave, the real consequences of a materialist analysis of the new epoch were defined essentially by the left communists who fought against the degeneration of the CI, in particular the German KAPD (Communist Workers Party). The interventions of the KAPC) at the Third Congress of the CI were all concerned with the tasks imposed on revolutionaries by the new period, and almost symbolically represent the fundamental split which was taking place in the workers’ movement of that time.
On the interpretation of the world economic crisis, the KAPD militant, Schwab, insisted on the fundamental difference between the period of capitalism’s ascendancy and its period of decline, and there was already an understanding that this historic decline did not signify a complete stagnation of the productive forces but a continuation of capitalism on a more and more destructive basis. “Capital rebuilds, preserves its profits, but at the expense of its productivity. Capital restores its power by destroying the economy”. Here already there are insights into the waste production, underutilisation of capital, and above all the cycle of crisis, war and reconstruction which are essential features of the decadent phase of capitalist society.
Of course, the left communists’ understanding of the historical moment in which they found themselves was necessarily limited by the fact that they had not long emerged from the old period; and it was further limited by the rapid onset of the counter-revolution which took a heavy toll of their organisations. In this sense, more lasting than the economic analysis put forward by the left communists of the early twenties was their intransigent insistence that the proletariat had to make a complete break with the habits of the old period - in effect, the habits of reformism - and adapt itself to the tasks imposed by the advent of the epoch of social revolution. It was on this materialist basis, and not because of their inherently ‘anarchist’ or ‘infantile’ nature, that the left communists rejected the opportunist tactics taken up by the International. Thus, at the Third Congress of the CI, while recognising that in the ascendant epoch it had indeed been necessary for the working class to organise parliamentary fractions, the KAPD now insisted that “to urge the proletariat to take part in elections in the period of capitalist decadence amounts to nourishing in it the illusion that the crisis can be overcome by parliamentary means.”
The same held true for the question of the unions: the KAPD pointed out that organisations which had been built to defend the working class in an epoch when genuine reforms were still possible were now not only unsuitable as instruments for making the revolution, but had actually become pillars of capitalist order which had to be smashed by the revolutionary working class. This was equally the case for the social democratic parties. The left communists therefore refused to engage in united fronts with what had become part of the state apparatus of the class enemy.
These analyses were not fully formed, of course, and still contained many inconsistencies - for example the KAPD’s illusion that you could replace trade unions with permanent ‘factory organisations’ of a revolutionary character, a position that expressed the influence of anarcho-syndicalism and thus of a form of trade unionism. Other weaknesses were also to play an important role - in particular the disastrous turn towards the theory that the October revolution had been a ‘dual’ or even a purely bourgeois revolution, a theory that completely negated the notion of the global decadence of capitalism. Ironically, but perhaps inevitably, a deeper understanding of the decadence of capitalism only emerged through the horrible experience of the counter-revolution, which reduced the authentic revolutionary currents to a few small groups trying to draw up the lessons of the defeat and to chart the main characteristics of the new period.
In the 1930s, which saw the definitive triumph of the counterrevolution and the emergence of the purest expressions of capitalist decay (Nazism, Stalinism, the war economy, etc), the fraction which developed the most coherent analysis of the epoch was the Italian left in exile around the review Bilan (i.e. ‘balance sheet’ - the balance sheet of the lessons of the revolutionary wave and of its defeat). Bilan’s application of the theory of decadence was central to the clarifications they made regarding many aspects of the communist programme, in particular their complete rejection of national movements anywhere in the world, since in the new period the bourgeoisie could only a reactionary role, both in the colonies and the metropoles.
The clarity attained by the Italian left can be measured by citing an article which appeared in 1934 (‘Crises and Cycles in the Economy of Capitalism in Agony’, Bilan 11, September 1934). The writer, Mitchell, traces many of the deepest trends of capital in its decadent epoch. Developing his argument on the basis of Rosa Luxemburg’s theory of capitalist collapse, Mitchell defined the decay of the capitalist mode of production as having commenced in 1912-14 and as a process in which “capitalist society, because of the acute nature of the contradictions inherent in its mode of production, can no longer fulfil its historic mission: to develop in a continuous and progressive manner the productive forces and the productivity of human labour. The revolt of the productive forces against their private appropriation, once sporadic, has become permanent. Capitalism has entered into its general crisis of decomposition”.
Mitchell points out the essential difference between the cyclical crises of ascendant capitalism and the periods of boom and slump in decadence. Whereas, in the former period, crises were necessary moments in the continued expansion of the world capitalist market, the saturation of the market which brought in the new era means that henceforward the crises of capitalism can only be ‘resolved’ through imperialist wars:
“In its decadent phase, capitalism can only guide the contradictions of its system in one direction: war. Humanity can only escape such an outcome through the proletarian revolution”.
With almost prophetic accuracy, the author goes on to discuss the probable developments of the period ahead:
“Whichever way it turns, whatever means it tries to use to get over the crisis, capitalism is pushed irresistible towards its destiny of war. Where and how it will arise it is impossible to say today. What is important to know and to affirm is that it will explode with a view towards the carving up of Asia and that it will be worldwide”.
Mitchell concludes with a warning against the capitalist alternative of ‘fascism versus democracy’, which was no more than a means to divert the proletariat from its class struggle and mobilise it for capitalist war. But the working class at that time had suffered too many defeats to heed the warnings of the communist fractions, and the fractions themselves had no illusions about the enormity of the defeat the class had been through.
Alongside the Italian left, the council communists (the remnants of the KAPD, the Dutch left and others) stood alone in their defence of internationalist principles in face of the imperialist butchery in Spain and World War Two. But while the council communists were the first to recognise that the ‘workers state’ in the USSR was in fact a form of state capitalism, they were theoretically hamstrung by their increasingly rigid adherence to the notion that October 1917 had been a bourgeois revolution; this prevented them from making the crucial realisation that state capitalism was a universal tendency of decadent capitalism. In America, Paul Mattick did begin to elaborate a theory of permanent crisis based on Grossman’s emphasis of the falling rate of profit as the basic determinant of the crisis, but his methodology led him into a number of aberrations, such as seeing state capitalism as a new mode of production with no imperialist dynamic, and thus, in a sense, progressive. Hence Mattick’s ambivalence on the nature of China, the war in Vietnam, etc.
The elaboration of communist theory after World War Two consequently found its best expression in those who attempted a synthesis of the contribution both of the Italian left and the German and Dutch lefts. The Gauche Communiste de France, with its publication Internationalisme, which split from those elements of the Italian left who were voluntaristically seeking to form a party in a period of reaction, was able to assimilate many of the German left’s insights about the relationship between the party and the workers’ councils, something Bilan had been less clear about. More important still, it formulated a profound analysis of the tendency of decadent capitalism towards statification, and was thus able to grasp the capitalist nature of Russia and its satellites without falling into the error or calling October 1917 a bourgeois revolution.
The GCF disappeared in 1 952 under the tremendous pressure of the counter-revolution that had only been reinforced by the second world war and the victory of ‘democracy’ over fascism. The group had not seen with sufficient clarity that the war had provided world capital with a temporary breathing space:
the enormous ‘boom’ of the 50s and 60s was based on the reconstruction of the war-shattered economies of Europe and Japan and a new global economic arrangement characterised by the overwhelming superiority of US imperialism. The startling growth-figures of this period led many sociologists, and even elements in the revolutionary movement, to theorise about a new ‘crisis-free’ capitalism and the ‘embourgeoisiement’ of the working class.
But in Venezuela in the mid-60s a small group was formed around one of the leading elements of the old GCF. This new group, Internacialismo, took the work of the latter a step further by describing the whole cycle of capitalism’s decadence: crisis, war, reconstruction, new crisis ... and, on the basis of this understanding, was able to predict the end of the boom, the opening of a new phase of open crisis, and an international resurgence of struggles by a generation of workers no longer paralysed by the terror and delusion of the counter-revolution.
This perspective was amply confirmed by the massive struggles of May-June 68 in France and the subsequent international wave of class movements, and by the visible deepening of the world economic crisis in the early 70s, which also brought about a sharpening of tensions between the US and Russian imperialist blocs: in sum, humanity was once again confronted with the historic dilemma between world war - which now meant the very destruction of the human race - and world revolution, the creation of a communist society.
The Internacialismo group was instrumental in the formation of Revolution Internationale in France, in the immediate aftermath of the May68 events. The main body of this pamphlet is a series of articles published in the early issues of Revolution Internationale (no.5, old series, and nos. 2, 4 and 5 new series), and itself constitutes a lasting contribution to the theory of decadence. But RI also played a key role in the formation of similar groups in other countries, and which came together in 1975 to found the International Communist Current.
Through the 70s and 80s, the ICC systematically charted the course of the crisis, uncovering the factors that have made it the longest, deepest crisis in capitalisms’ history, a true expression of the death agony of this system. It followed the development of imperialist antagonisms, in particular the offensive of the US bloc after the Russian invasion of Afghanistan, the growing encirclement of the USSR which had the ultimate aim of stripping the latter of its status as a world power. At the same time, the ICC described the uneven but real development of class consciousness through this period, in two further international waves of class struggle(1978-80, 1983-89).
By the end of the 80s, decadent capitalism had reached an important watershed. The continuation of the workers’ struggle was blocking the path to world war, but the proletariat was not yet mature enough to raise the question of revolution; as a result, the exacerbation of the economic crisis was opening up a general process of social decomposition: capitalist society was rotting on its feet, falling apart at the seams. This process produced, and was considerably accelerated by, the sudden collapse of the Russian bloc and the consequent dislocation of its western rival, historical events that definitively opened up the final phase of capitalist decay, the phase of generalised decomposition. In the absence of imperialist blocs, world war has been taken off any foreseeable agenda - but this has in no way mitigated decadent capitalisms’ penchant for militarism and imperialism. On the contrary. As the huge slaughter in the Gulf at the beginning of 1991 showed quite clearly, the very process of decomposition itself, with its train of local and regional conflicts, ‘police actions’ by the great powers, of famines and ecological catastrophes, constitutes no less a threat to the survival of humanity.
The ICC is not the only organisation in the proletarian movement today which holds to the theory of decadence. But it is the only one that has been able to identify and analyse this final
phase. The text ‘Decomposition, final phase of the decadence of capitalism’ was first published in our International Review 62 in the summer of 1990. (See Appendix 2)
As can be seen from this brief historical sketch, the theory of decadence is not an invention of the ICC, but an authentic inheritance from the entire marxist tradition, and it is the indispensable basis to any consistent revolutionary activity. Without an appreciation of the epoch in which it is operating, the programme of a proletarian political organisation can have no material foundation, no orientation for its analyses or its intervention within the class. Without a grasp of the decadence of capitalism, there can be no firm defence of the class frontiers which separate the proletarian from the bourgeois camp. This was demonstrated very painfully by the collapse of the ‘Bordigist’ International Communist Party (Communist Programme) in the early 80s. Although this current claims to be the genuine heir of the Italian left tradition, it rejected the notion of decadence which had been so crucial to the work of the Italian Fraction in the 30s. In particular, it rejected the idea that since the decadence of capitalism was a global phenomenon, there could no longer be any progressive role for ‘national liberation’ movements in the underdeveloped regions. Reiterating Bordiga’s sterile theory about the ‘invariance’ of marxism since 1848, the ICP saw a revolutionary significance in all kinds of national liberation wars - all of which were in fact proxy wars between the two imperialist blocs or between other local and regional imperialist sharks. By the beginning of the 80s the ICP’s support for Palestinian nationalism led a faction within if to pass over into the camp of leftism pure and simple, and this in turn resulted in the implosion of the whole international organisation.
On the other hand, groups which have attempted to defend class positions on such issues as the national or trade union questions while repudiating the notion of decadence have fared little better. The case of the Groupe Communiste Internationaliste is instructive here: having started life with the claim of being ultra-orthodox marxists, this group has, through its fervent rejection of nearly all the theoretical pillars of left communist politics for the last fifty years, drifted more and more into modernism and anarchism. A similar fate has befallen certain councilist groups who have been equally hostile to the notion of decadence. This should be a timely warning for all those who follow the recent fashion of denigrating the theory of decadence and of looking for alternative explanations and periodisations - for example those who misapply the concept of the ‘formal and real domination of capital’, developed by Marx to describe certain important changes that were already well underway within the ascendant period. The ICC has responded to this ‘fashion’ with a series of articles in its International Review this series represents, in fact, a further development of the theory of decadence [1] [2].
The work of understanding the decadence of capitalism continues. But the theory is above all a guide to action, to the intervention of revolutionaries in a historical situation where the very survival of humanity is at stake. This pamphlet begins with a long historical investigation of the decadence of previous class societies (a chapter which has never been published in full in English before),and it enters into number of complex theoretical issues about the characteristics of the capitalist economy in this epoch. But this work has no academic pretensions whatever; its only aim in investigating the reality of present day capitalism is to arm the militant struggle against it.
[A brief not on the Footnotes]
The statistical references contained in the main body of this pamphlet were compiled in the 1970s and are now obviously 'out of date', but only in the sense that the continuing decay of this society has confirmed the tendencies that they illustrate. The ICC's International Review has published regular updates on the 'progress' of the capitalist crisis, and we recommend the reader to refer to these articles.
[1] [3] See issues 48, 49, 50, 54, 55, 56, 58, 60.
In order to define the decadence of capitalism, our approach will be as follows:
- by looking at the main social transformations of the historical process we will draw out the general concept of the decadence of a mode of production; we will then apply this general concept to the specific case of capitalism and try to deduce the political consequences that flow from it.
- and, in doing this, we will, like Marx, consider first “the material transformation of the economic conditions of production”, and secondly “the legal, political, religious, aesthetic or philosophical - in short, ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out”.
The form of social organisation at the beginning of humanity was what Marx
called ‘primitive communism’. Despite important local differences in climatic, historic,
or other elements, the essential traits of primitive societies were the
collective ownership of the means of production (essentially the land) and
collective labour in agriculture and the hunt, the products of which were
shared equally amongst the whole population. The idea that private property is
something inherent in human nature is just a myth popularised by bourgeois
economists since the 18th century; its aim is to present the capitalist system
as the most natural one, the one that best corresponds to human nature.
On the other hand, these
egalitarian relations were not the product of an ideology of brotherhood or the
work of a God anxious to ensure equality between his creatures. It was humanity’s
lack of power faced with a natural environment that could be as hostile as
man’s techniques were feeble, which imposed this need for social cohesion,
forcing men to live in communities that used their means of production in an
egalitarian way. The egalitarian ideology which did exist was a consequence of
these relations and not their cause:
“The mode of production of material life dominates in general the development of social, political and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men which determines their existence, on the contrary, their social existence determines their consciousness (Marx, Preface to a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy).
In the same way, the disappearance of primitive communism wasn’t the result of ideological changes but of the disappearance of the material conditions which had engendered such a society. If one examines the way in which these egalitarian societies were transformed into societies of exploitation, with the appearance of classes and of private property, it becomes evident that it was the result of progress in the techniques of production.
We will leave aside the cases where this ‘progress’ was the result of the civilising work of European colonial massacres from the end of the 15th century onwards.
In different regions of the globe, and in various local historic conditions, primitive communist societies disintegrated and ceded their place either to the asiatic mode of production or slavery.
Slavery When a community exhausted the fertility of its territory, or when its game had departed, or when its population grew too large in relation to its means of survival, it was obliged to extend or remove its domination to new territories. In regions where the density of population was relatively high - in the Mediterranean for example - such expansion could only be made at the expense of other communities.
In the beginning, wars provoked as a result of these movements could only take the form of gratuitous massacres or cannibalism. Their sole aim was to seize the land of conquered peoples. As long as the level of social productivity only permitted a man to produce just enough for his own individual subsistence, the conqueror had no interest in integrating new mouths into the hungry community. It only became feasible for a conquered people to work for their conquerors, for free and by force, while at the same time producing enough for their own subsistence, when the productivity of labour had reached a certain level [1] [4].
Primitive communist relations were thus abandoned in order to make use of a higher level of productivity in a context of wars and conquests.
This badly understood economic system was in general the result of the need of certain communities to face up to the problems posed by nature in certain regions (aridity, floods, monsoons, etc). In such regions communities were very quickly forced to study the cycles of nature and to undertake irrigation works to assure their livelihood. The complexity of these works, the technical knowledge they required, the need for an authority to coordinate them, engendered layers of specialists (priests, versed in the study and observation of nature, were often at the origin of these castes). Charged with a specific task in the service of the community, these specialists - appearing to be the creators of new wealth - tended to constitute themselves into a ruling caste. They progressively appropriated the social surplus at the expense of the collectivity. The development of the productive forces transformed these servants of society into exploiters.
The ‘Asiatic’ mode of production left the communal relations of production unchanged, as basic cells of production. The ruling class only appropriated the surplus created by the work of these communities. But a first transition from primitive communism had been made. The need to apply new techniques of production resulted in the emergence of new relations of production and the abandonment of the old.
The introduction of new techniques of production later on did away with the remnants of egalitarianism in these societies. Thus, for example, the problem of fertilising the land, the necessity to create a more intimate link between the worker and the earth, often led to to an abandonment of the systematic redistribution of plots according to custom or the needs of families. The necessity to ensure a greater continuity in the maintainence of plots, or the weight of fiscal pressures, resulted in the passage from communal to private property. And with the latter, inequality slowly developed, until a part of society had to work on the richest plots for a fraction of the resulting production. Society became entirely stratified, taking the form of a society of serfdom or feudalism.
But whether they gave way to slavery or oriental despotism (and the latter in its turn to serfdom), communist relations caved in under the pressure of the progress of the productive forces, which could no longer adapt to the old framework.
“At a certain stage of their development the productive forces enter into collision with the existing relations of production or with the property relations within which they worked hitherto” (Marx, ibid).
The result of a development of the productive forces in the particular regions where one people conquered another, slavery allowed the appropriation by one social group of the surplus labour realised by the rest of society. The owners of slaves, as a ruling class avid for profit and privileges, became the motors of the development of the productive forces. However, this development was strictly limited to wars of conquest, mainly taking the form of a growth in the number of slaves and of great works that facilitated the pillage of conquered countries. It was on this basis that ancient Greece and Rome developed their civilisations.
The Roman slave economy - the decadence of which opened the door to feudalism - was founded on the pillage and exploitation of conquered peoples. The latter furnished Rome with its essential means of subsistence (food, tribute and slaves). It often happened that the goods imported were produced under different modes of exploitation, such as the Asiatic mode of production. But the metropole itself subsisted on slavery, the latter being applied above all in wide-scale exploitation (olive groves and stock farming) and in the great works.
These works often served military needs, being used in the exploitation of colonies (roads, viaducts, etc). At the same time they reflected the concern to ensure the luxury of the ruling class.
Thus political power was most often connected with the triumphant military caste. Economic prosperity was therefore closely dependent on the warlike capacities of the metropole.
The great development of Roman civilisation corresponded to its period of victories and conquests. Its zenith was reached when Rome dominated the Mediterranean world and pocketed the profits. In the same way the onset of Roman decadence was marked in the second century AD by the end of this expansion, and in the third century by the Empire’s first defeats (in 251 the Emperor Decius was defeated and killed by the Goths; in 260 the Emperor Valerian was taken prisoner and humiliated by the king of Persia. In the course of the third century revolts in the colonies broke out simultaneously for the first time).
The difficulties of maintaining such a gigantic empire with the limited technical means available at that time explains in part the end of Rome’s expansion. But above all it was the gap between the economic productivity of Roman slavery and that of its colonies (which often developed a superior productivity under the Asiatic mode) which ensured that the revolts in the colonies would ultimately be successful.
Slave relations of production were characterised by low labour productivity. In the conditions of the epoch, a growth of productivity required the improvement of methods for working the earth - the utilisation of the plough, the development of fertilisation and the creation of an intimate link between the worker and the soil, providing the worker with a motive for using these techniques of production. But such progress demanded the abandonment of slavery, in which the worker is maintained by his master whatever his productivity, and in which only the fear of punishment forces the slave to produce, so that he works with the least care possible.
Slavery was only profitable as a means of exploiting conquered peoples. Once these conquests stopped or diminished, once the sources of booty, tributes and slaves dried up (in turn leading to a rise in the value of slaves), slavery transformed itself into an unprofitable system, a fetter on the development of production.
The need to pass on to new productive relations led, in the metropole, to the appearance of feudal types of exploitation, in which the great proprietors ceded much land to free families in exchange for a part of their produce. But the surpassing of slavery also involved an attack on the privileges of the ruling class. The ‘collision’ between the development of the productive forces of society, and the relations of production that had existed until then, precipitated Rome into its phase of decadence.
The development of production slowed down or stopped: “They (the wealthy Romans) ‘gleaned’ the products of the mines and undermine the soil, allowing pastures or forests to disappear in semi-arid regions. Manpower was exploited without a break, stimulating discontent and apathy in work. They even forbade the application of new methods, and neglected irrigation works and drainage in regions where they were essential....War, epidemics and starvation reduced the population of the Empire by a third. The death rate was perhaps even higher in Italy itself during the course of the third century" (Shepard B Clough, Grandeur and Decadence of Civilisations, Editions Payot p140)
Following slavery or the Asiatic mode of production, the feudal system allowed a new scope to the productive forces of society for centuries.
In autarkic feudal relations, work on the soil attained unequalled levels of improvement (amelioration of ploughing, shoeing of work animals, of harnessing - at the head or neck instead of the belly - development of irrigation and of fertilisation, etc). Furthermore, and above all, the perfecting of agricultural labour was accompanied by a considerable development of artisan work. The latter existed as a simple appendage of the agricultural economy: supplying instruments of labour and certain items of consumption, essentially for the ruling class (mainly clothing and weapons).
The craftsman benefited from the growth of resources available to the noble class thanks to the development of agricultural productivity. This last factor figured all the more as the noble class wasn’t engaged in accumulation - the particular character of the bourgeoisie - but used all its profit for personal consumption.
But from the twelfth century on feudalism had begun to reach the limits of the possibilities for extending cultivatable surfaces.
“We have enough indices of the lack of land at the end of the thirteenth century to suggest that the extension of cultivatable surfaces was inferior to the national growth of population; and with the exception of certain places, it was probably insufficient to compensate for the tendency for labour productivity to fall. The pressure from land shortages after 1200 in Holland, Saxony, Rhineland, Bavaria and the Tyrol was one of the factors which gave birth to the migrations towards the east, and we can say that at the end of the fourteenth century the limits of acquiring soil from forest land were already reached in the north east of Germany and Bohemia” (Maurice Dobb, Studies in the Development of Capitalism, p 59).
“The contemporaries of St Louis, and in certain regions those of Philippe de Bel, saw the development of the soil pushed to its limits. The most audacious reclamations were attempted because it was always necessary to feed more mouths and because, not knowing any other way of augmenting the yield, the space cultivated always had to grow. Permanent marshes and wasteland seemed to disappear. Woods shrank. The marshes and fens of the English coast were drained, cleaned, exploited to the limit of what was technically possible...” (J Favrier, De Marco Polo a Christopher Columbus, p 125)
From then society could only break out of its impasse through a new development in the productivity of labour. Now the latter had more or less attained its extreme limits in the context of family artisan production. Only the passage from individual labour to the labour of a number of associated workers, to a more complex division of labour and the utilisation of more complex means of production could in these conditions permit the necessary growth of productivity.
This was possible because the development of artisan work under feudalism also contributed to a revival of the towns, which were the basis needed for more collective forms of labour.
But, fundamentally, the feudal framework was the negation of the conditions which could allow for a real development of this economic form:
- feudalism was founded on the life-long attachment of men to their means of production as well as to their lord, whereas manufacturing demanded great mobility of labour power, and thus a separation of the worker from the means of production;
- feudalism was a system of local power, of autarky, of the closed fief, with innumerable tolls to pay on the passage of commodities through different feudal estates. The manufacturer, by contrast, needed a mobility of raw materials, of commodities in general, so that he could concentrate in one place of production the products from a thousand different places, and ensure the freest possible distribution of his own commodities;
- finally, manufacturing production must base itself on the accumulation and the concentration of profits in order to obtain, replace and then expand the machinery which allows for production based on the division of labour. It requires therefore a spirit of success through work and the right to accumulate the rewards of the latter. Feudal privileges, on the other hand, were based first on the capacity to make war, and after that solely on heredity.
At the level of the capacity to work, the lord was equal or inferior to the serf. Hence feudal society’s contempt for work, which was seen as a form of debasement.
The feudal lord made it a matter of honour to display his ability to consume his entire revenue. The feudal economy ignored and condemned accumulation aimed at the growth of production, an attitude which barred the way to the development of manufacture.
“We can consider that the beginning of the fourteenth century marked the end of the mediaeval economy’s period of expansion. Up till then, progress had been continual in all spheres ... But by the first years of the fourteenth century, all this came to an end. Although there wasn’t a regression, there was no advance either. Europe was, as it were, resting on its laurels: there was stability on the economic front...the proof that the previous economic thrust had been interrupted was the fact that foreign trade ceased to expand...In Flanders and Bravante, the drapery industry maintained itself without increasing its traditional prosperity until around the middle of the century, then it began to go rapidly downward. In Italy, most of the great banks which had dominated the money markets for so long fell into a series of reverberating bankruptcies ... the decline of the fairs of Champagne date from the first years of the century. This was also the time when the population stopped growing, and this constituted the most important symptom of the state of a stabilised society which had reached the final point of its evolution.”
(H. Pirenne, Histoire economique et sociale du Moyen Age, PUF, p 158).
Just as in slavery, the decadence of feudalism meant famines, since the growth of the productive forces was far inferior to the growth in population. Famines were then followed by epidemics, which spread rapidly because of the poor nutrition of the population. Thus from 1315 to 1317 a terrible famine desolated all of Europe, followed thirty years later by the Black Death, which between 1347 and 1350 wiped out one third of Europe’s population.
“It’s true that it was precisely then that countries which had been outside the main areas of economic development, like Poland and especially Bohemia, began to participate in it more fully. But their belated awakening didn’t result in any important consequences for the western world as a whole. It was thus clear that society was entering a period when more was being conserved than produced, and when social discontent testified to both the desire and the incapacity to improve a situation which no longer corresponded to men’s needs.” (Pirenne, op cit, p 158)
Feudal decadence began in the fourteenth century, continuing until the overthrow of its last juridical traces by the bourgeois revolutions of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in England and France. But from the fourteenth century new relations of production were beginning to dominate society: capitalism. Developing out of a struggle against the old feudal fetters, it was the main beneficiary from the morass of the fourteenth century, and was to allow a great revival of economic life.
[1] [5] The development of wars was an active factor in the abandonment of egalitarian social relations: conditions of semi-permanent warfare demanded the emergence of a layer of specialised warriors who tended to appear as the suppliers of wealth to the collectivity and who thus began to establish hierarchical relations within the community, with the rest of the community ensuring their upkeep. But in itself this factor only became important when the growth of productivity permitted the passage to slavery.
The development of the productive forces has two aspects:
1. The growth of the number of workers incorporated into production at a given level of productivity;
2. The development of labour productivity amongst a given number of workers.
In a system in full expansion, one can see a combination of both. A system in crisis is a system which has reached it limits in both aspects at the same time.
We can speak of an ‘external limit’ to the expansion of a system (its incapacity to enlarge its field of action) and of an ‘internal limit’ (the incapacity to go beyond a certain level of productivity). Consider the case of the end of slavery, of the Roman Empire. The external limit was constituted by the material impossibility of enlarging the extent of the Empire. The internal limit was the impossibility of raising the productivity of the slaves without overthrowing the social system itself, without eliminating their status as slaves. For feudalism it was the end of land reclamation, the incapacity to find new arable lands, which acted as the external limit, while the internal limit was its inability to raise the productivity of the serfs, or of the individual artisan, without transforming them into proletarians, without introducing labour associated by capital: that is, without the overthrow of the feudal economic order.
The approach of these two types of limits are dialectically linked: Rome could not expand its empire indefinitely because of the limits of production; inversely, the more difficult it was to expand, the more it was obliged to develop its productivity, thus pushing it more rapidly towards its extreme limits. Likewise feudal reclamations were limited by the level of feudal techniques, while the scarcity of land encouraged more ingenuity in productive activities carried out in the towns and the countryside. This in turn pushed feudal productivity to the border of capitalism.
In the final analysis it is the limits on the level of productivity within the old society which lead it into the morass. It is this productivity which is the true measure of the level of development of the productive forces; it’s the quantitative expression of a certain combination of human labour and means of production, of living and dead labour [1] [6].
To each stage of development of the productive forces, that is, at each overall level of productivity, there corresponds a certain type of relations of production. When this productivity approaches its last possible limits within the system which corresponded to it, and if the system is not overthrown, society enters into a phase of economic decadence. Then there is a snowball effect: the first consequences of the crisis transform themselves into factors accelerating the crisis. For example, at the end of Rome as well as in the decline of feudalism, the drop in revenues of the ruling class pushed the latter to reinforce the exploitation of the workforce to the point of exhaustion. The result in both cases was the growing apathy and discontent of the labourers, which only accelerated the decline in revenues.
Likewise the impossibility of incorporating new labourers into production forced society to support inactive strata who constituted yet another drain on revenues.
A similar phenomenon was the galloping devaluation of money at the end of the Empire as well as at the end of the Middle Ages: “Rome had hoped to cover its governmental expenses by increasing taxation, but when the proceeds proved insufficient it was necessary to resort to inflation (at the end of the Second Empire). This first expedient had to be repeated from time to time in the course of the third century, certain monies being devalued to 2 percent of their face value. The monetary unity of the Empire was destroyed; each town and each province issuing its own money”( Shepard B Clough, op cit, p 141).
And at the end of the Middle Ages: “In a world where the mass of money became insufficient, the wage-bill (of soldiers used for protection against robbery or in wars - ICC note) increased the need for precious metals; thus the temptation to overvalue the cash in circulation. The rulers used their authority to diminish the weight of coins, so that a coin valued at 2 sous henceforth contained less pure silver and more lead, but was now worth 3 sous. This was inflation!”( J Favier, op cit, p 127).
Parallel to these economic consequences the crisis causes a series of social convulsions which in their turn impede an already enfeebled economic life. The development of productivity systematically conflicts with existing social structures, rendering impossible any new development of the productive forces. the need to go beyond the old society is put on the agenda.
“A society never expires before all the productive forces contained within it have been developed” (Marx, op cit).
In fact it should be noted that no system has developed ALL the productive forces - in the proper sense of the term - which it may contain in theory.
On the one hand, the economic consequences that we have seen and the series of social catastrophes which the first great economic difficulties cause are so many fetters preventing the system really attaining its absolute limits. We must bear in mind that an economic system is the ensemble of relations of production that men have been led to establish, independently of their will and in accord with the level of productive forces, to PROVIDE FOR THEIR ECONOMIC NEEDS. Before the last instrument of production has seen the light of day, if production has started to grow less quickly than the needs of the population, the system loses its historic reason for existence, and everything in society tends to push against its confines.
On the other hand, under the pressure of the productive forces, the economic foundations of the new society begin to develop within the old. This only applies to past societies where the class which overthrew them was never the exploited class. Feudalism grew up within the Roman empire. The first feudal plantations in Rome were often headed by old members of the municipal senate put to flight by a state which made them responsible for the collection of taxes.
Likewise, at the end of feudalism, members of the nobility became businessmen, and in the towns - often in struggle against local lords - developed the first manufactories, prefiguring capitalism.
These first ‘centres of the future system’ (great Roman plantations, bourgeois towns) were mostly born as the result of the decomposition of the old system. They attracted all kinds of elements trying to escape the system. But from being the results of decadence, these centres quickly transformed themselves into factors that hastened it along.
Material conditions permit the passage to a new type of society, whose premises already exist within the old society, and their pressure is sufficient to begin the foundation of a new system.
“New relations of production have never been put into place before the material conditions of their existence has been discovered within the old society” (Marx, op cit).
It is not enough that production approaches its final limits within the old society. It is also necessary that the means to go beyond the latter already exist or are in the process of formation. When these two conditions are historically realised, society’s adoption of new relations of production is on the agenda. But the resistance of the old society (of the old privileged class, the inertia of customs and habits, ideologies, religion etc), and the gap that may exist between the realisation of these two conditions, means that such transformations do not take place in a progressive, linear manner, but through a series of regressions, catastrophes, and qualitative leaps.
The phase of decadence of a system is that period in which such a historic leap has not been made; it is the expression of a growing contradiction between the productive forces and the relations of production; it is the sickness of a body whose clothes have become too tight.
[1] [7] It is this relation which under capitalism will be partially expressed by the organic composition of capital: c¼v constant capital over variable capital.
When the economy trembles, the whole superstructure that relies on it enters into crisis and decomposition. The manifestations of this decomposition are the characteristic elements of the decadence of a system.
Beginning as consequences of a system, they then most often become accelerating factors in the process of decline. Many a bourgeois historian, having seen the latter phenomenon, deduces from it that the superstructural elements are actually the main causes for the ending of a civilisation.
In this examination of superstructural elements, we will look at four phenomena which can be found both in the decadence of slavery and the decadence of feudalism. We will see that these are no historical coincidences, but definite symptoms of the decadence of a system.
These phenomena are:
1) the decomposition of the ideological forms that reigned in the old society;
2) the development of wars between factions of the ruling class;
3) the intensification and development of class struggles;
4) the strengthening of the state apparatus.
In a society divided into classes, the dominant ideology is necessarily the ideology of the dominant class. The scope for the enrichment and development of its ideological forms depends on the real capacity of the ruling class to persuade the whole of society to accept its rule. A society is only prepared to accept a given ideology as long as the economic system it is based on corresponds to that society’s needs. The more an economic system ensures prosperity and security, the more the human beings who live by it will identify with the ideas that justify it. In conditions of expansion, the injustices inherent in the economic relations can appear as no more than ‘necessary evils’; the belief that everyone can benefit from the system permits the development of democratic ideologies, above all within that part of society which benefits from it the most - the ruling class (the regime of the Republic corresponded to the most flourishing period of the Roman economy; in expanding feudalism, the king was merely a suzerain, elected as the first among equals).
Law itself is relatively little developed because the system corresponds sufficiently to the objective needs of society for most problems to be resolved by allowing things to take their course.
The sciences tend to develop, philosophy leans towards rationalism, towards optimism and confidence in mankind. Since the ugly side that belongs to any exploitative society is relatively well hidden by the state of prosperity, ideologies are less encumbered by the need to hide reality and justify the unjustifiable. Art itself tends to reflect this optimism and usually has its best moments in the periods of economic development (what is referred to as the ‘golden age’ of Roman art corresponds to the main period of the growth of the Empire, for example; similarly in the prosperous days of the 11th and 12th centuries, feudalism went through an immense artistic and intellectual renewal.
But when the relations of production turn into a straitjacket for the life of society, all the ideological forms corresponding to the existing order lose their roots, are emptied of content, and are openly contradicted by reality. In the decadence of the Roman empire, the ideology of the political power took on an increasingly supernatural and dictatorial form. In the same way feudal decadence was accompanied by the reinforcement of the idea of the divine origins of the monarchy and the privileges of the nobility, which were being severely battered by the mercantile relations being introduced by the bourgeoisie.
Philosophies and religions express a growing pessimism; confidence in mankind gives way to a fatalism and obscurantism (eg the development of Stoicism then of Neoplatonism in the Lower Roman Empire: the first talked about the elevation of man through pain, the second denied the capacity of man to grasp the problems of the world through reason).
The end of the Middle Ages saw the same phenomenon:
“The period of stagnation saw the rise of mysticism in all its forms. The intellectual form with the ‘Treatise on the Art of Dying’, and above all, ‘The Imitation of Jesus Christ’. The emotional form with the great expressions of popular piety exacerbated by the influence of the uncontrolled elements of the mendicant clergy: the ‘flagellants’ wandered the countryside, lacerating their bodies with whips in village squares in order to strike at human sensibility and call Christians to repent. These manifestations gave rise to imagery of often dubious taste, as with the fountains of blood that symbolised the redeemer. Very rapidly the movement lurched towards hysteria and the ecclesiastical hierarchy had to intervene against the troublemakers, in order to prevent their preaching from increasing the number of vagabonds...Macabre art developed... the sacred text most favoured by the more thoughtful minds was the Apocalypse.” (Favier, op cit, p 152f).
All this reflected the growing gap between the relations reigning in society and the ideas about them which men had hitherto held to.
The only ideologies which could really develop in these periods was law, on the one hand, and, on the other, the ideologies which announced the new society.
In a society divided into classes law can only be the expression of the interests and will of the ruling class. It is the totality of rules that permit the proper functioning of the system of exploitation. Law goes through a period of growth at the beginning of the life of a social system, when the new ‘rules of the game’ are being established; but also at the end of a system, when reality rends the system ever more unpopular and inappropriate, and the ‘will’ of the ruling class becomes the most important thing keeping the old relations going. Law then represents the necessity to reinforce the oppressive framework necessary for the survival of a system that has now become obsolete. This is why law developed both in Roman decadence and during the decline of feudalism (Diocletian, the greatest Emperor of the Lower Empire, was also the one who produced the greatest number of edicts and decrees. Similarly from the 13th century onwards, the first collections of customary laws began to appear).
Parallel to this phenomenon there appear ideas advocating new types of social relations; they take on critical, rebellious and finally revolutionary forms. They are the justification for the new society. This phenomenon was particularly evident from the 15th century on in western Europe. Protestantism, particularly the form preached by Calvin, was a religion which, as opposed to Catholicism, allowed for the lending of money on interest (crucial for the development of capital); which taught spiritual elevation though work and glorified the successful man (thus opposing the ‘divine’ origins of the privileges of the nobility and justifying the new situation of the ‘parvenu’ bourgeois businessman); which put in question the supernatural character of the Catholic church (the main feudal landholder) and advocated the interpretation of the Bible by man without any intermediary. This new religion was an ideological element which announced and hastened the rise of capitalism.
Similarly, the development of bourgeois rationalism, whose ultimate expression was in the philosophers and economists of the 17th and 18th centuries, expressed the revolutionary element of the conflict into which society had entered.
Decomposition of the old ruling ideology, the development of the ideology of the new society, obscurantism against rationalism, pessimism against optimism, coercive law against constructive law, here, as Marx said, we find “the juridical, political, religious, artistic, philosophic, in short, the ideological forms through which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out”.
The prosperity of a system of exploitation allows there to be relative harmony between the exploiters, and thus there can be ‘democratic’ relations between them. When the system ceases to be viable, when profits diminish, harmony gives way to wars between the profiteers. Thus, in parallel to the brigandry that characterised the end of the Roman Empire and the Middle Age, there was a proliferation of wars between factions of the ruling class.
In Rome from the second century onwards there was a series of wars fought by knights, bureaucrats and army chiefs and senators and patricians:
“Between the years 235 and 285, out of the 26 Emperors who succeeded each other to the throne, only two died a natural death, and at one moment there were up to 30 claimants to the throne” ( SB Clough, op cit, p 142).
At the end of the Middle Ages wars between nobles took on such proportions that the western kings were forced to forbid them, and Louis IX went as far as to forbid the bearing of arms. The Hundred Years War was a phenomenon of this type.
When the ruling class can no longer escape the contradictions of its system and sees its profits declining irreversibly, the most immediate solution is for each faction to grab hold of the wealth of their rivals; or at least to seize control of the conditions of production which allow this wealth to be produced (for example, the fiefs of the feudal epoch).
In the decadence of a system there are three phenomena which make the intensification of class struggles one of the main characteristics of these periods of decline:
- the development of poverty: we have already shown that the end of slavery and feudalism were regularly marked by famines, epidemics and the generalisation of poverty. We have seen what consequences this had within the privileged classes, but it was obviously the oppressed classes which suffered these scourges most intensely; this provoked them into more and more frequent riots and revolts;
- the strengthening of exploitation: we have also shown how in a system in decadence, productivity can less and less be increased by technical means, so that the ruling classes are increasingly tempted to palliate this through the super-exploitation of labour. The latter is used up to the point of exhaustion. There is a whole growth in punishments for those who fail to do enough work...
Added to the poverty and suffering they are already enduring, this last factor can only accentuate the tendency towards the generalisation of struggles between the exploited and the exploiters. The reactions of the toiling classes are so violent, and in the end so damaging to the goal of increasing productivity, that at both in the end of the Roman Empire and in the late Middle Ages, there is a tendency to replace punishments by measures aimed at giving the labourers an ‘interest’ in their work (the emancipation of the slaves and the serfs) [1] [8]
- the struggle of the class that bears within it the seeds of a new society: in parallel to the revolts of the exploited, there is a development of the struggle of a new class (the great ‘feudal’ landowners at the end of the Roman Empire, the bourgeoisie at the end of feudalism), which begins to establish the bases of its own system of exploitation, which sap the bases of the old system. These classes are thus led to wage a permanent combat against the old privileged class.
During the course of this struggle, the revolts of the labouring classes always provides the force that these new classes themselves lack in their effort to supplant the old structures, now become completely reactionary (it’s only in the proletarian revolution that the class that carries within itself the germs of the new society is at the same time the exploited class).
All these elements explain the fact that the decadence of a society necessarily leads to a decisive renewal of class struggles. Thus, in the Lower Roman Empire:
“the situation created by the deficiencies in production, an ever-increasing taxation, the devaluation of the currency and the growing independence of the large landowners had the consequence of further accentuating the political and social disorganisation and of leading to the disappearance of the principles that regulated relations between men...impoverished landowners, ruined merchants, labourers from the towns, colons, slaves, rioters and deserters from the army resorted to pillage in Gaul, Sicily, Italy, North Africa and Asia Minor. In 235 a wave of brigandry swept through the whole of northern Italy. In 238 civil war reigned in North Africa. In 268 the colons of Gaul attacked numerous towns, and in 269 a slave revolt broke out in Sicily” (Clough, op cit, p 142).
“The breadth of the social movements affecting the Latin west in the 5th century is impressive. They shook all regions and especially Brittany, western Gaul, the north of Spain and Africa...” (Lucien Musset, Les Invasions, p 226).
It was the same at the end of the Middle Ages:
“From the end of the 13th century labourers’ riots shook the Flemish towns. At the time of the Hundred Years War and the Italian divisions, it was the upsurge in urban misery that gave rise to the troops of vagabonds that wandered the countryside. It was very often the same kind of people in different countries, men with no land who became men with no work: the ‘Jacques’ of the French plains, the Tuchain of Languedoc, the Lollards of the English midlands, the Mallotins of Paris, the Coquillards of Bourgogne. Daring tribunes exploited their distress and put these revolts at the service of the political ambitions of a social group or individual. Etienne Marcel wanted to impose on the Dauphin the tutelage of a faction of the bourgeoisie...Van Atevelde had exploited the misery of the Flemish labourers, Cola di Rienzo, a ‘tribune of the people’ did the same with the lower orders who had been devastated by the excesses of the Roman aristocracy. In Florence, the revolt of the Ciompi, a hunger revolt, in the end served the interests of the Medicis...Thus, this stagnation, this fruit of divisions, war and social disorder led to pillages, riots and massacres...” (Favier, op cit p 137. See also Pirenne, op cit, p160f).
The revolutions of Cromwell in 1649 in England and the French revolution of 1789 were the spectacular culmination of the struggles provoked by the decline of feudal society and the birth of capitalism.
The history of economic systems can only be the history of the men who live within them. The development, conservation and supersession of a given society are the work of groups of men driven to act according to their economic position within a system. The capacity of a system to sustain itself is above all relative to the strength of the class which draws most profit from it; the strength of a new society is similarly related to the strength of the class which has the most interest in it.
Thus, it’s in the action of social classes that we see the concretisation of the objective forces that have plunged society into a contradiction. At a given moment, the class conflict is none other than the conflict between the reality of the development of the productive forces and the existing relations of production.
If law represents the interests and will of the ruling class, the state is the armed force charged with ensuring that the law is obeyed. It is the guarantor of the order required for the exploitation of one class by another. Faced with the economic and social disorders that characterise the decadent phase of a system, the state can only be reinforced. “The development of the function leads to the development of the organ”.
- Against social disorder: having emerged as the armed force of the ruling class, the state is essentially the servant of a class. However, it’s around this ‘servant’ that we see the clearest crystallisation of all the interests of the ruling class: its task is to maintain an overall, general order. In this sense it has a wider view of the functioning of the system - and of its necessities - than that of the individuals who compose the privileged class. Separated from society as a whole because it is an organ of oppression in the service of a minority, it is also distinguished from this minority by its character as a single, unified organ in contrast to the diversity of the factional or individual interests of the exploiters. Furthermore, the privileges of the state bureaucracy are closely linked to the proper functioning of the system as a whole. The state is thus not only the force that can attain a sufficiently global view of the economy, it is also the only one which has an immediate and vital interest in its good functioning.
Thus in periods of decadence the state is reinforced because it has to deal with a growing number of revolts by the oppressed class, but also because it is the only force that can ensure the coherence of the ruling class when it is pushed towards dispersal or tearing itself apart.
The development of the power of the Roman Emperor, above all from the second century onwards, as well as that of the feudal monarchy, had a real justification both in their respective struggles against the revolts of the oppressed and in their attempts to defend the reigning order by restricting the struggles between factions of the ruling class. The Emperor Septimus Severus (193-211) ended up confiscating “the properties of senators and urban businessmen in order to procure the necessary funds for paying the soldiers who assured his safety and power” (Clough); the Capetian monarchy developed at the expense of the great feudal lords.
In most cases, wars also constitute a powerful factor in the strengthening of the state apparatus. Only the state authority can carry out the regroupment of forces that war demands; the state always emerges stronger from such tests. This factor played a very important role in the strengthening of the feudal monarchy, particularly in France.
- Against economic disorder: It is notable that there was a very strong development of state interventionism both during the decline of the Roman empire and during the waning of feudalism:
“As far as production was concerned, he (the Emperor Dioticien, 284-305) imagined that it could be stimulated by a sort of ‘directed economy’; he regulated the activity of the ‘colleges’, controlled the exploitation of the great estates and established control over prices. Finally, the tax rate was revised and the production of money regulated in order to try to stabilise the currency” (Clough, p 143).
As for the feudal royalty, it strengthened itself by creating a powerful interventionist administration. The development of the bureaucracy was such that the feudal courts ceased to be itinerant and settled down in one city: Paris, Westminster, Pamplona, Moscow. The king used his own functionaries (baillifs and seneschals in France) whose economic tasks grew more and more throughout the realm.
When the economic relations of a society become a calamity for those involved in them, only armed force can keep them going. As the armed force and ultimate crystallisation of the laws of a system, the state then tends to take the economy in hand.
Everything in a decadent society pushes this phenomenon forward: the parasitic costs that derive from the need to maintain an economy that is no longer viable leads to a huge growth in fiscal burdens. Only a strong state can extort such funds from a population that is already hungry and on the verge of revolt. Both the later Roman Emperors and the feudal kings found that this task was one of the main bases for the strengthening of their powers. The economy was no longer in accord with the necessities imposed by social reality; economic initiative no longer had a natural guide in the search for prosperity and harmony with the rest of society. State power, state intervention then became the only means for trying to prevent the paralysis of the economy, a collapse into total disorder. Both at the end of slavery and the end of feudalism, there was a development of tendencies towards the bureaucratisation of society and the systematic control of the individual.
This tendency reached particularly frightful proportions in the period of the Lower Roman Empire:
“Everyone was dissatisfied with their situation and tried to escape from it. The peasant deserted the countryside, the craftsman abandoned his craft, the decurion fled the municipal senate. The state power had no remedy for these problems: all it could do was to try to tie everyone to their condition and close the doors through which they could escape.
The watchword was ‘everyone at their post’ or Roman culture would perish. It was a state of siege, a perpetual siege of life. Social conditions, professions were made hereditary. There was the establishment of a real caste regime; and this wasn’t something primitive or spontaneous, but new, political, imposed from above” (F Lot, Le Fin du monde Antique et le Debut du Moyen-Age, p 109).
Some labourers were marked with red hot irons to stop them abandoning their jobs. The right of pursuit was made general.
This same necessity for state interventionism appears at the end of feudalism. But there was an important difference between the economic action of feudal royalty and that of the Lower Empire.
As it decomposed slavery gave way to a system of autarky, a particularly fragmented economic system. The attempt to centralise and strengthen the state on the one hand, and the development of feudalism on the other, were two simultaneous but quite contradictory phenomena. Feudalism, by contrast, would be superseded by capitalism, that is by a system that required an increasing level of concentration and integration of economic life. The centralisation and interventionism of the feudal state, which resulted from the necessity to shore up a disintegrating feudal system, thus objectively constituted a means for developing the bases of capitalism. Several fundamental factors forced the monarchy to take up this dual historical role:
1) the monarchy often had to call on the support of the bourgeois towns to bolster its power;
2) the interests of the dominant exploiting class, the nobility, could be in relative accord with those of the rising bourgeoisie;
3) the growing strength of the bourgeoisie, which had by the end of the 15th century created the bases of capitalism, enabled it to impose a partition of power on the aristocracy.
The economic measures taken by Edward II, Edward III, the mercantilist policies of Henry VII in England, the economic developments realised under Louis XI in France, the protectionist actions favourable to the development of industry taken by most of the French and English kings from the 14th century onward, as well as the acceptance of bourgeois parliaments by the two monarchies, are all evidence of the eminent role played by the feudal monarchy in the process of the primitive accumulation of capital.
But it would be absurd to see the feudal monarchy from this angle alone. The monarchy remained essentially feudal, in fact it was the last rampart of feudalism. This is attested by facts such as: the constant struggle between the king and the bourgeois parliaments; the defence of noble privileges by the monarch (in France only the commoners paid taxes); the defence of the corporations; the struggle against Protestantism - the ‘religion of the bourgeoisie’ - in France; finally, the very fact that the bourgeoisies in England and France had to resort to revolution to permit a real development of capitalism.
Despite this dual role played by the feudal monarchy, the inexorable reinforcement of the state was aimed essentially at maintaining the feudal system and was a typical feature of a society in decline.
If the image of a society in decadence is that of a body which is pushing against a garment that has become too tight, the development of the state apparatus is simply the attempt of the garment to strengthen itself so that the mounting pressure from the body doesn’t tear it to pieces.
Decomposition of the dominant ideology, the development of wars and revolutions, the reinforcement of the state, these are the most salient characteristics of a society in decadence, a society in which the productive forces are finding it harder and harder to develop. The economic system ceases to be a historic necessity and instead becomes a fetter that plunges society into growing barbarism.
[1] [9] This phenomenon has a particularly interesting significance: when an economic system is at the end of its tether, it is often obliged to abandon certain of its juridical aspects in order to preserve what is essential: the real relations of production
Decadence and open crises in capitalism in the twentieth century are phenomena which are linked together but distinct; not identical but interdependent.
Our object here is not to study these moments of crisis (for example, 1929 or 1938); it is not to ascertain whether capitalism now is beginning to undergo these types of crisis. We shall address ourselves to the task of showing that capitalism has been in a state of senility, of decadence, since 1914 and that the magnificent 'rates of growth' of which it boasts, especially since World War 2, in fact merely hide the agony of a system which is less and less able to create the conditions for its own reproduction.
But what exactly is the meaning of this state of decline or decadence?
In the first part of this article (Revolution Internationale, Old Series, no 5) we attempted a definition of this phenomenon, its causes and its manifestations, as it occurred in past societies, particularly at the end of Roman slave society and west European feudalism.
We can briefly summarise the general idea which came out of this study in the following way.
Contrary to those who would like to hold an evolutionist view of history which presents progress in human society as a continual, uninterrupted, always ascendant process, no past society disappeared at the time of its zenith. It is only after a more or less long period of decline that the pre-capitalist societies gave way to new forms of social organisation.
The zenith of a society constitutes its limit. It corresponds in effect to that period wherein men are best able to obtain the maximum development of their material wealth given the existing level of technology, and the presence of certain social relationships. It is this degree of development which marks a certain stopping point. It cannot be superseded without the utilisation of new techniques of labour, without abandoning the hitherto prevalent relations of production and consequently without the overthrow of the social order founded on these relations. It is this zenith which makes the advent of the new society an objective necessity.
If the course of history were a harmonious process of constant evolution, then social upheavals would have taken place following these moments of apogee. But history is the history of class struggle. The material necessity of a social upheaval develops in accordance with the development of productive forces, as an objective process independent of the will of men. However, the upheaval itself is the work of men and more precisely that of a social class. Its effective realisation consequently depends on objective and subjective conditions which determine the will and also the possibility for action by this class.
Now, these conditions do not exist at the zenith of a social system. Following their apogee, before disappearing, all past societies have undergone a long period of crisis and convulsion. The old structures decompose; new forces attempt to assert themselves. This period of disintegration and of gestation, this era of barbarism, this 'era of social revolution', is what constitutes the decadent phase of a society.
What are the factors which, while they do not appear at the moment of apogee, make decadence an irreversible necessity?
A totality of social relations which have linked men together for centuries cannot be transcended in a day. Man never abandons a tool which has served him in the past until it has proven unable to serve him any longer. A social form cannot prove its 'uselessness', its historic obsolescence, except through the misery and barbarism which its maintenance provokes. Years of famine, plague, war, and anarchy were necessary before men were forced to begin to abandon slavery and feudalism. Only such events, engendered by the decadence of a society, can bring to an end centuries of customs, ideas and traditions. Collective consciousness always lags behind the objective reality which lies before it.
Parallel to these elements, there are two objective factors which are necessary for the realisation of the advent of the new society, also lacking at the time of society's zenith: on the one hand, the weakening of the power of the ruling class, and on the other hand, the appearance of a new historical project and of social forces capable of realising it.
The power of the ruling class and its attachment to its privileges are powerful factors in the conservation of a social system. But the power of this class has its roots in the efficiency of the system which it dominates. The existence of classes is the result of a certain necessary division of labour in a given moment of the development of the techniques of production. The strength of their power resides in the first place in the unique and indispensable relations of production existing under their rule. The zenith of an economic system is also the most stable period in the power of the ruling class. Consequently, the downfall of that power can only take place with the downfall of the relations of production, in the course of the system's decadent phase. All the attempts to artificially maintain this power by the state and political totalitarianism, (attempts which, as we shall see, have always been undertaken and which are significant symptoms of decline), are in fact the result of the decomposition of this power.
Finally, a man never definitely abandons a tool which has been indispensable to him before finding another tool to replace it. In order that a mode of production be abandoned (when it is this mode which has hitherto provided the means of subsistence for a society), it is necessary that there emerge within the old society the forces indispensable for the establishment of new relations of production. In past societies the class bearing the new order did not exist (or existed only in embryonic form), as long as the society had not yet entered into its decadent phase. (The great feudal properties did not really develop in Ancient Rome except under the Late Empire; similarly under feudalism the bourgeoisie did not come into its own until the beginning of the fourteenth century.)
These three principal elements brought about by the decline of a system are certainly not the only ones which explain the causes of decadence in Roman and feudal society. They do, however, enable us to understand the inevitability of a period of decadence for past societies. It remains for us to see whether these same reasons exist under capitalism. But first, it is necessary to recall the principal manifestation of periods of decadence.
All these manifestations can be observed in the state of generalised crisis affecting the whole structure of social life.
1) At the economic level: (the infrastructure of a society).
Production increasingly comes into conflict with constraints which are none other than the social relations of production themselves. The rhythm of the development of the productive forces slows down, sometimes even stops altogether. Society undergoes economic crises the gravity and extent of which grow larger each time.
2) At the level of the superstructure:
Since in all societies, including the present one, material subsistence is the foremost social question, in the last instance it is always the relations of production which have determined the form and content of different social structures. When these relations are undermined, they must progressively involve in their downfall the whole edifice which is based upon them. When such a state of crisis develops at the economic level, all other areas of social life are necessarily affected.
It is here that we must look for the real roots of the famous 'crisis of civilisation'. The idealist vision of history loses itself in studies of 'the decline of moral standards', of the destructive or beneficial influence of this or that philosophy or religion; in short, it seeks in the domain of ideas, of contemporary modes of thought, the reasons for these crises. Without denying the important influence of ideas in the course of events, it is, nevertheless, certain that, as Marx said:
“One does not judge an individual by the idea he has of himself. One does not judge an epoch of revolution according to the consciousness which it had of itself. This consciousness is explained rather by the contradictions of material life, by the conflict between the social productive forces and the relations of production". (Marx, Preface to a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy).
3) In the domain of ideology
The preservation of the system becomes a painful absurdity and gives less and less rationality to the ideology which justifies it. Ideology decomposes, the old moral values run down, artistic creativity stagnates or functions in opposition to the status quo, there is a development of obscurantism and philosophical pessimism.
4) In the domain of social relations
Decadence is manifested by:
a - The development of conflicts between the different factions of the ruling class. The conditions for extracting profit; and even its quantity, become more and more difficult to maintain; those property owners who want to assure their subsistence must do so at the expense of other members or fractions of their class, thereby abandoning all possibility of co-operation.
b - The development of struggles between antagonistic classes: the struggles of the exploited class which undergoes more and more misery because exploitation is pushed to the extreme by the exploiting class; the struggle of the class which is the bearer of the new society, (in past societies, this class has always been distinct from the exploited class), and which comes up against the forces of the old order.
5) In the political domain
Faced with this state of crisis, in which the ruling class is unable to ensure its political power in the same way as before, the apparatus of order, the State, the ultimate crystallisation of the interests of the old society, tends to become strengthened and to extend its jurisdiction to all areas of social life.
In the first part of this article we showed how these characteristics appeared at the end of Roman slave society and during the decline of feudalism. We showed how the totality of these phenomena constitutes an unequivocal manifestation of the decadence of a society.
But how are we to go about defining decadence in capitalist society? Analogous symptoms do not allow us to diagnose the same illness for different individuals, unless the latter are of the same species or the same kind. Given the character of decadence in past societies, can we consider capitalism in the same light? Do the old symptoms and causes retain their validity when applied to capitalism?
On the level of material production, the subordination of the social system to the development of the productive forces is a law which remains valid under capitalism. As long as humanity lives under the 'reign of necessity', as long as it has not reached the stage of abundance which will permit it to eliminate problems of material subsistence or at least relegate them to a secondary place - a stage from which humanity is still a long way away - the first function of an economic system remains the development of the productive forces. What is more, in generalising the competitive market economy, capitalism (this system in which capital that does not develop is condemned to disappear or to pass into other hands), has made this necessity of development still more powerful.
It is thus certain that for capitalism, just as for feudalism and slavery, an insufficient development of the productive forces represents, in historical terms, a deadly impasse.
But if this condition came about could it, or must it, represent a phase of decadence as in other societies?
Capitalism remains first of all a society divided into classes; secondly, a society where men continue to live under the domination of their economic needs, and thus submit unconsciously to their social structures. We find in capitalism certain essential traits of past societies, and in particular those which make the appearance of a phase of decadence an inevitability. These characteristics can be summarised as follows: the lagging of collective consciousness behind reality, the dependence of the ruling class's power on the efficacity of productive relations, the weight and inertia of customs and habits deriving from the old society, the impossibility of attaining a new social form before the old one has proven its obsolescence, and before a new historical project has begun to germinate within society. Like the societies which precede it, capitalism thus can and must undergo a phase of decadence.
However, alongside these traits which are common to all societies based on exploitation, capitalism also has characteristics which radically distinguish it from slavery and feudalism. To begin with, the system which constitutes the negation and the supercession of capitalism is not itself a system of exploitation. Thus, the decadence of capitalism contains new specifics in relation to the other systems.
Socialism is the first system in history which does not grow up within the society which it is to supersede. Feudal economic relations were born within the Late Roman Empire in the great estates which become more or less independent from the central power; capitalism was born within the burghs and then the towns of feudal society. In both cases, the future ruling class progressively substituted itself for the former.
By contrast, the proletariat has no possibility of constructing a new society within capitalism. As an exploited class, the direct source of the ruling class's profit, it cannot push forward its own historical project without totally destroying the power of that class. In contrast with the past, the coexistence of the two systems is excluded. Since capitalism is the first system to have integrated the whole of world production into one circuit which incorporates the whole planet, socialism in one country is impossible. This means that the decadence of capitalism must be a decadence far clearer, far more violent than ever before.
Feudalism was able to survive in France even if under a monarchical form, until the eighteenth century, thanks to the prosperity of the bourgeoisie which allowed the partial satisfaction of economic needs which feudalism itself was no longer able to meet. This is not the case for capitalism which hurtles to its grave on its own. Its gravedigger is not a potentially useful competitor with which it can accommodate itself, however provisionally, but a mortal enemy engendered by centuries of oppression and with whom all compromise is impossible. All the consequences of capitalist decadence fall on society with a violence and directness that cannot be moderated. Thus, on the one hand this decadence has a more intense character than ever before, and on the other hand, it is much shorter: the greater evidence of its effects imply a much more abrupt period of reaction.
In contrast with other revolutionary classes in history the proletariat does not appear during the decadent phase of the previous system of production, but right at its beginning. When capitalist society reached its zenith, the proletariat was already fully developed as an economic class; when the system began to enter the period of its decline, its gravedigger was already at the height of its numerical strength. The end of capitalism will not be attained, as in the past, when the architect of its destruction is born and develops in the dung heap of the old world in decline.
Two other factors help to shorten the decadence of capitalism:
a - the lesser importance of ideological relations. Under the system of wage labour and capital there is no religious, political or personal relation to mediate the relations of exploitation (contrary to those which were produced under slavery and serfdom). A much more direct link between social life and economic life proper emerges. Therefore, a more rapid reaction occurs on the social level to the economic difficulties which characterise the period of decadence.
b - Finally and above all, living for competition alone (on a national and international scale), capitalism cannot exist without developing.
It is true that no society in the past could continue without ensuring in one way or another a certain development of the productive forces. But in the past this development was never truly an intrinsic feature of the existing relations of production. The profits and privileges of the members of the ruling classes did not directly depend on their capacity to ensure their own economic expansion. The profit which they extracted from the labour of serfs or slaves was dedicated to their personal consumption and to luxury. It is only incidentally that it served to develop production. When these systems began to come up against their economic contradictions, there had to be a slowing down of growth and even stagnation because otherwise the ruling classes would immediately have been weakened and poverty-stricken, and the economic life of society would have been paralysed.
Under capitalism, if the growing accumulation of capital cannot be ensured, the whole process of extracting profit and then the whole production process itself, finds itself blocked. This is one of the essential traits of the capitalist system.
Now the principal characteristic of the decadence of a system is the growing impossibility for society to develop economically without abandoning the existing relations of production. Therefore it is difficult to conceive of a long period of decadence for capitalism and it is clear that the decadence of a society is an historical phenomenon, the causes and principal manifestations of which can be fixed precisely. The decadent period of capitalist society reveals an analogous nature to the decadent stages of preceding societies, but for various reasons, capitalist decadence seems to have to be shorter and more intense than the period of decadence was for other systems. Having said this, it is necessary now to confront this analysis with the reality of capitalism.
It could be said that we should have begun this study at this point. For a variety of reasons, nothing could be less true. The concept of the decadence of capitalism could only really have been of interest to revolutionaries confronted with the beginning of the period startlingly landmarked by the outbreak of World War I. Indeed, the split between the 2nd and 3rd Internationals during World War I took place in the context of a debate concerning the end of the ascendant period of capitalism and its entry into the period of 'war and revolution'. However, since then throughout more than fifty years of triumphant counter-revolution, and precisely because of the counter-revolution, revolutionary theory has lacked the breadth and depth of insight which would have been necessary to understand the transformations world reality has undergone.
Today, at the end of this ideological tunnel, it is unfortunately too often the case that the different currents claiming to be part of the revolutionary proletarian movement are still divided between those who have an excessive relish for 'new implications' or a 'new reality' (marxism has been superseded) and those who maintain a religious attachment to old texts and ideas in reaction to the former tendency (cf. the 'Bordigists' of the International Communist Party with their cry of 'nothing new under the sun'; their 'invariability' of the revolutionary programme since 1848). Between these two poles but falling simultaneously into both currents, we find the Trotskyists sticking to the last letter of Trotsky's 'Transitional Programme' yet ready to follow every new faddish theory, (self-management, neo-capitalism, third worldism), as soon as it becomes clear that such theories can help win a few recruits. The result of this is that the concept of 'decadence', of which Marx only gave a rough outline, still remains an idea too hazy and surrounded by confusion for us to have avoided going over its definition at the outset of this study.
It may seem illogical to begin this 'confrontation with reality' by analysing the superstructure of capitalism (ideology, politics, social conflict), and not the economy, the first being in the final analysis a mere product of the latter. However, we will use this method in order to make our argument easier to follow. Indeed, while it is in general easy to recognise in modern capitalism the superstructural manifestations of a decadent epoch (every modern moralist feels obliged to talk from time to time of the 'crisis of civilisation', etc.), we rarely find a clear and lucid analysis of the underlying economic process. Consequently, the majority of explanations of our 'crisis of civilisation' do not go beyond idealist empiricism. By examining initially the 'superstructure', not only do we make the study simpler to understand by beginning with the most simple aspects; but, in order to solve the economic problem later we can enlarge an important argument here, thereby achieving the coherence vital to any scientific enquiry.
We cannot enter fully into a study of the links between the dominant ideology and the life of capitalism in the last decades here. We can simply establish the extent of decomposition of the dominant ideology.
It is hard to specify what constitutes capitalist ideology as such: firstly, because it has absorbed elements of the ideological heritage common to class societies for thousands of years. Secondly, under such a blindly mechanical system, the dependence of social relations vis-a-vis the means of production is such that ideology as a means of preserving these relations has not played such a central role as in the past, even if it remains extremely important. One can nevertheless, affirm that 'the work ethic', 'the glorification of social progress', 'confidence in and respect for institutions' or 'faith in the capitalist future' constitute the foundations of the dominant ideology. All these values have been violently eroded over the last fifty years as a result of the atrocities of capitalist life. It is more and more difficult to sing the praises and to glorify the values of a society which in fifty years has seen 100 million people killed as a result of wars whose uselessness has become more and more obvious; a society which shows itself to be incapable of allowing two men out of three to obtain the most elementary means of subsistence; a society in which the two greatest economic powers spend on arms alone the equivalent of the income of one third of humanity; a society in which in the most privileged areas of the planet, the price of the right not to die of hunger is a monstrous dehumanisation of daily life.
The recourse to gigantic works of ideology by the likes of Hitler, Mussolini, Stalin, Mao, etc...(phenomena which can be compared with the cults of divinisation of the emperors of decadent Rome and of the monarchs of late feudalism); the crisis of the Church; the difficulties of capitalism in abandoning methods of teaching which have for a long time been ill-adapted to its technical needs; as well as the crisis of the university, the main centre of the ruling ideology (cf. 'Le mouvement etudiant' and 'Critique' in Revolution Internationale, old Series, no 3), all these are acute expressions of the first symptom of decadence: the decomposition of ideology.
This decomposition has over the last twelve years or more appeared in a spectacular fashion among youth. The present generation's disgust of the modern world, which results in various attempts to take flight in a kind of 'marginalism' or attitude of confrontation, has been dealt with thousands of times by the newspapers and media. This 'leap forward' has actually come rather late, (more than fifty years after 1914 and the revolutionary waves of 1917-23). And one reason for this is the constant time-lag between ideological forms and the evolution of socio-economic reality. It was necessary to await the arrival of a generation which has not lived through World War 2 or suffered the violent blows of the counter-revolution which followed the 1917-23 revolutionary wave. Also, this late development can be explained by the economic stability which the system enjoyed as a result of reconstruction after World War 2. The first signs of weakness were not felt until a few years ago, in particular among the young, the first social layer to be affected by problems of employment.
Philosophically, there is less and less room for ideas of making society more 'harmonious'. Intellectuals today either see themselves as revolutionaries or are disillusioned, pessimistic and indifferent. Obscurantism and mysticism have again become fashionable (cf. Revolution Internationale, old Series, no 6).
In the sphere of art, decadence has manifested itself in a particularly violent way, and it would take a long time to discuss the evolution of art faced with a world that has become an aberration. As in other periods of decadence, art, if it does not stagnate in an eternal repetition of past forms, seeks to take up a stance against the existing order, or is very often the expression of a cry of horror.
When the world of ideas undergoes such upheavals it is the sign that something is breaking down at the level of material production.
With the decline of capitalism, conflicts increase between factions of the ruling class. Although the exacerbation of competition between capitals within one nation is at times mitigated by concentration (which may reach the point at which the state takes control of the whole productive process), competition at the level of the world market has increased to a point of insanity:
1914-18: 20 million dead 1939-45: 50 million dead.
Since World War 2, through the medium of national liberation wars, the war between different capitalist blocs has never stopped and has brought with it millions more deaths, sacrifices on the altar of world domination. Today the capitalists are unable to extract enough profit to be able to divide up the world on a co-operative basis. The decadence of previous societies led to the devastation of whole countries; today, the whole planet is threatened with destruction.
In the nineteenth century the struggles of the working class generally were of a reformist nature, that is to say they sought to ameliorate the condition of the class within the system (the Paris Commune, in that it was dramatically revolutionary, was more an 'accident of history' than a sign of the times). During the course of these struggles, the proletariat acted essentially, and almost solely, as an exploited class. With the outbreak of World War I these conflicts underwent a radical transformation both in their extent and their content. The movement which developed was no longer confined to a few factories or to one town. The whole of Europe was set alight by the most powerful proletarian movement of all time. Its content was no longer the reform of the system but its radical overthrow. The Russian fraction of the world proletariat managed to destroy the apparatus of the bourgeois state and momentarily seize power for itself.
After three years of the war, capitalism had clearly proven its historic inability to continue to assure the progress of humanity. Simultaneously the proletariat transformed its struggle from one of an exploited class into a revolutionary struggle which for the first time in history, and on a world scale, represented the candidature of an exploited class for the leadership of humanity. Since that time, everything has had to change on the 'social' terrain of capitalism.
The revolutionary wave of 1917-23 was defeated and the Russian proletariat, isolated and alone, was strangled by the hands of some of its own leaders. But, despite the weight of the defeat and the confusion sown for decades by the Soviet experience, the 'proletarian menace', far from having disappeared remains a fact of life in capitalist society. Asserting itself in sporadic, isolated, proletarian uprisings, and through its day to day struggles, the working class represents a formidable presence throughout the last fifty years of history: all the states of the world have indeed become organs in defence of the workers, in other words, organs for ensuring the strict containment of the revolutionary class. The old forms of working class organisation, the unions, have become an essential element integrated within the state apparatus to assist in the containment of the revolutionary class.
And if the 'prosperity' which followed World War 2 has led some people to believe that 'the class struggle is over', the new elan of workers' struggles following 1968 throughout the world has forcefully reminded everyone of the continued existence of the revolutionary working class and announced that mankind is on the brink of the most important revolutionary wave in history.
The strengthening of the state is one of the most striking manifestations of decadence in past societies. It is also one of the principal characteristics of capitalism since 1914. State capitalism, which is actually the most senile form of the system, but which the capitalists and bureaucrats the world over take pleasure in calling 'socialism', is simply the ultimate expression of this tendency.
The state played an important role in the early days of industrial capitalism at the time of the primitive accumulation of capital. This has led some pundits to assert that modern state capitalism, particularly in the underdeveloped countries, is the sign of a new development of world capitalism. However, the least amount of historical understanding enables one to see why the statism of our time has nothing in common with the timely interventions of the bourgeois state in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
In this century, statism is no longer a subsidiary aspect of the system but a continuous and irreversible process. Its basis is no longer rooted in the struggle against the hangovers of pre-capitalist, feudal relations but in capitalism's struggle against its own inner contradictions. The direct causes of the strengthening of the state in our epoch express all the difficulties which result from the definite inability of capitalist relations of production to adapt to the development of the productive forces. In effect, the state has attained the measure of its power today because it is the only capitalist institution capable of taking charge of companies in deficit; realising the economic centralisation and the 'rationalisation' which the intensification of international competition on a saturated market imposes on each nation; prosecution of wars and the preparation for wars, which has become the prime necessity for the survival of each nation; assuring the cohesion of social mechanisms which are constantly threatening to fall apart.
In short, the task for the state has become one of holding together by force (of which it has a monopoly) an edifice which of itself tends more and more towards collapse.
As to state capitalism in the underdeveloped countries, there is no possibility that this is a less senile form of the system than in the advanced countries. These countries are not 'young capitalisms', but the weakest sectors of world capital. Thus they feel the internal contradictions of world capitalism with greater violence, and thus they must more quickly and more energetically assume the statified form of the system.
The case of the Soviet Union does not contradict the decadent character of statified capitalism. Here, as elsewhere, we have the exhaustion of the limits imposed by capitalism, and the draconian measures which this calls forth on the part of each nation if it is to survive on the world market. This forms the basis for the strengthening of the state. Here, as elsewhere, the weakness or non-existence of private capital have been the principal accelerators of the process. The fact that these two principal factors are, in the case of Russia, the result of a situation engendered by the failure of a proletarian revolution does not in any way modify the essentials of the problem. These particularities only explain one thing: why the Soviet Union was the first country to concretise what has become a general tendency throughout the world.
Decomposition of ideology, of the dominant values; discord of social relations at all levels; antagonisms that reach the level of periodic paroxysms as much within the ruling class as between the ruling class and the exploited class; reinforcement of the apparatus of coercion, the state, and integration of the whole of social life under its direct control; we find in modern capitalism all the traits of the decomposition of a civilisation, all the characteristics of a system in decadence.
But what about the infrastructure, at the level of material production ? As we have shown, such phenomena of crisis have never appeared without being accompanied by economic decadence. From the marxist point of view, problems appearing in the superstructure of society are in the final analysis only signs of a crisis in material production.
From 1914 to 1939 the statistics, as we shall see, were very clear and few could deny that this was a period of stagnation. However, since the end of World War 2 the course of history would seem to have changed profoundly; the symptoms of a 'superstructural' decadence continued to develop but according to existing statistics capitalism has undergone an unprecedented phase of growth.
Has marxism perished in the barbarism of World War 2 ? Are we living under a 'neo-capitalism' ? Or are these manifestations of crisis merely warning signs of a decadence which is still a long way off ?From 1953 to 1969 the gross national product of the United States (calculated by volume and per inhabitant) multiplied by 1.4. Similarly the GNP in Italy and Germany multiplied by 2.1; the French GNP doubled, and the Japanese multiplied by 3.8. Where then is the 'decadence' of capitalism?
Even if a large part of this production is used only for military purposes; even if the gap between industrialised countries and underdeveloped countries grows, it seems obvious that 'the productive forces have not stopped growing'. Even if the evolution of political structures indicates the decomposition of the dominant value system, the development of class antagonisms as well as conflicts within the ruling class are all evidence of a 'crisis of civilisation' - a decline of capitalism at the superstructural level - it seems that many marxists find it difficult to speak of 'decadence in the capitalist system' when they see so much 'economic expansion'.
Marx wrote: "No social order is ever destroyed before all the productive forces for which it is sufficient have developed..." (Marx, Preface to a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy)
A certain way of interpreting this passage led Trotsky, for example, to write at the beginning of his Transitional Programme (1938):"The economic prerequisite for the proletarian revolution has already in general achieved the highest point of fruition that can be reached under capitalism. Mankind's productive forces stagnate".
Trotsky was describing a reality that was more or less borne out by the statistics of the time. But apart from the realities of 1938, to prove that humanity has entered an age of social revolution and therefore the phase of capitalist decadence, must one hold that the productive forces have definitively stopped growing? And when twenty years later the same statistics show a relatively strong growth in world production must one then come to the opposite conclusion? In short, for a society to have irreversibly entered its period of decline, must the productive forces have entirely stopped growing? The problem raised by Marx in the Preface to a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy is in fact the question of defining the economic conditions in which the passage from one form of society to another becomes possible.
Marx's answer can be summarised in this way: the relations of production which men enter into for the social production of their means of existence and which constitute the real basis of their society, correspond to a given degree of development of the productive forces. In the course of history, the full development of these forces necessitates important and repeated changes in these relations of production.
For a social form based on new relations of production to be viable, a corresponding evolution in the productive forces must have taken place. If these forces are not 'sufficiently developed', there is no objective possibility for a new system of production to arise and survive. The problem is to determine what 'sufficiently developed' entails, and what is the maximum development of productive forces for which the old 'social order... is sufficient' and which once attained makes a new society possible and necessary. The marxist response does not refer to any particular quantitative level, determined without reference to the economic mechanisms (zero growth included). On the contrary, it refers to a qualitative level of relationship which links the relations of production themselves and the development of the productive forces.
"At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production or - this merely expresses the same thing in legal terms - with the property relations within which they have operated hitherto...Then begins an era of social revolution." (Marx, Preface to a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, our emphasis).
It is the appearance of this definitive and irreversible 'conflict' and not a halt in the development of the productive forces which opens 'the era' of the decadence of the old society. Marx states this criterion clearly: "From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters." (Ibid).
Marx's statement must be understood in this sense: a society never expires before the development of the productive forces has begun to be definitively checked by the existing relations of production. According to the marxist view, the period of a society's decadence cannot be characterised by a total and permanent halt in the growth of the productive forces but by the definitive slackening of this growth. Absolute halts in the growth of the productive forces do, in fact, appear during the phases of decadence. But these stoppages appear only momentarily in the capitalist system because the economy cannot function without a constantly increasing accumulation of capital. They are the violent convulsions which regularly accompany the progression of decadence.
All social changes are the result of the deepening and prolonged collision of the relations of production with the development of the productive forces. If we defended the hypothesis of the definitive and permanent halt in this development, the deepening of this contradiction could only be demonstrated if the outer bounds of the existing property relations were 'absolutely' receding. However, it happens that the characteristic movement of the different periods of decadence in history (including the capitalist system) tends rather in the direction of expanding these frontiers up to their final limits than towards their restriction.
Under the aegis of the state and under the pressure of economic and social necessities, the system's carcass swells while casting off everything that proves superfluous to the relations of production, everything not strictly necessary to the system's survival. The system is reinforced but at its last limits.
The freeing of the slaves under the Late Roman Empire; the freeing of the serfs at the end of the Middle Ages; the partial liberties which the declining monarchy had to grant to the new bourgeois cities; the reinforcing of the central power of the crown, and the elimination of the 'nobility of the robe' completely dominated by the king; and likewise, in the capitalist framework, the attempts at economic planning; the efforts to try to relieve the burden of national, economic frontiers; the tendency to replace bourgeois parasites with efficient salaried 'managers' of capital; policies such as the New Deal and the continued manipulation of certain mechanisms of the law of value - all are evidence of this tendency to expand the juridical framework by laying bare the relations of production. There is no halt in the dialectical movement after a society has reached its apogee. This movement is qualitatively transformed but it does not end. The intensification of the contradictions inherent in the old society necessarily continues and for this reason the development of the imprisoned productive forces must continue even if it is at the slowest rate.
From an economic standpoint, what characterises the decadence of a given social form is therefore:
- An actual slowing down of the growth of the productive forces with respect to the rates which would have been technically and objectively possible without the obstacle of the relations of production. This slow-down must have an inevitable and irreversible character. It must be caused specifically by the perpetuation of the relations of production which hold the society together. The discrepancy between actual development and possible development of the productive forces can only widen. This discrepancy thus appears increasingly clear to the social classes.
- The appearance of increasingly profound and widespread crises. These crises create the subjective conditions necessary for social revolution. In the course of these crises the power of the ruling class is profoundly weakened, and through the objective intensification of the necessity for its intervention, the revolutionary class finds the preliminary bases for its strength and unity.Our problem is therefore to find out whether these two phenomena characterise the capitalist system in the period from World War I to today.
While from 1850 to 1913 the volume of world trade increased by more than tenfold [1] [10], "from 1919 to 1936-38, world trade increased by only 7.4 per cent (1913 = 100 per cent; 1936-38 = 107.4 per cent), and the level of trade in industrial products was lower in 1936-38 (92.2 per cent) than on the eve of World War I. It must be added that in 1950, the world economy after great difficulty caught up with the 1938 trade level; in other words, world trade stagnated from 1938 to 1950". [2] [11]
From 1914-1929 During World War I, production in the European countries decreased by more than one third and world production by 10 per cent. Never before had capitalism experienced such a decline in production .
Following the war and up until the 1929 depression, capitalism enjoyed a period of prosperity due to the reconstruction of the economies destroyed by the war and the completion of the expansion of the two young capitalist countries - the United States and Japan. But Europe lost its predominant place in the capitalist world and would never really recover from the collapse caused by 'the great war'. In spite of reconstruction, in 1929 Englandhad not yet regained its pre-war level of exports. Its position as world banker slowly eroded. Germany, the hardest hit, collapsed or stagnated. [3] [12]Compared with the relative decline of Europe, the United States and Japan enjoyed an undeniable prosperity. Indebted to Europe at the beginning of the war, the United States came out of the war as Europe's creditor and, in addition, increased its production by almost 15 per cent. But this expansion was already suffering from the effects of a lack of markets: the sum of all the positive balance of payments during those ten years (1919-1929) was less than the amount of capital mobilised a short time before for the extension of the railways, (which was practically completed in 1919). [4] [13] From 1919 to 1929, although the index of industrial production rose by almost 60 per cent, the number of workers decreased from 8.4 million to 8.3 million. From 1910 to 1924, 13 million acres of cultivated land reverted to prairieland, grassland or grazing land. In addition, the United States could no longer rapidly expand into new territories but only into zones already conquered by the warring powers, which meant 'dividing' those markets. The changes in the distribution of Argentina's imports from the big powers from 1919 to 1929 is, in this respect, particularly significant. [5] [14]
The American share almost doubled while the English share decreased by almost half. The same thing happened with American expansion into Latin American and Canada. Japanese foreign expansion developed in the same way . In British India from 1913 to 1929, the British share of its imports fell from 64.2 per cent to 42.8 per cent while the Japanese share rose from 2.6 per cent to 9.8 per cent [6] [15].
From 1929 to 1938 The Great Depression of 1929 was to the whole world what World War I was to Europe. This time world production fell by one third. The decline was three times greater than during the war; recovery would not be as rapid. World non-military production did not regain its 1929 levels until World War 2. Figures for world trade have already been given. Production in the leading world power collapsed.
Only the countries which had begun massive armaments production (Japan, Germany and the USSR) experienced a certain growth in their production.In view of the two extraordinary drops in production rates, linked together by a period of reconstruction and followed by a period of stagnation until World War 2, it is undeniably clear that the growth of the productive forces was drastically held back from 1914 to 1940.
But does this slowdown mean that capitalism has definitively entered its decadent phase or is this a serious but temporary slowdown in a general growth cycle which was only interrupted at Sarajevo the better to begin again at Yalta?
After its triumphant progress in the nineteenth century, its regular and irreversible conquest of one country after another, the imperialist expansion of the capitalist metropoles came to an almost total standstill at the beginning of this century. Capitalism had penetrated all countries and the different capitalist powers had entirely divided up the world among themselves.
World War I demonstrated the impossibility for any power to find a zone still untouched by capitalism in order to assure its expansion. Germany, which arrived relatively late for the 'conquest' was forced to provoke history's first world war in order to carve out a place for itself commensurate with its economic power. After the war, Japan and the United States, as we have seen, could assure their expansion only at Europe's expense.
After 1914, the world would be divided and re-divided according to the balance of power, but no really new geographic expansion could be carried out. Economic growth in capitalism's ascendant phase was characterised by the increasing importance of colonial markets in world trade. The importance of these markets continued to grow statistically from 1914-18. From 1914 to 1929 it only slowed down; from 1929 to 1938 it even slightly revived (see graph below). Only in the course of World War 2 was this tendency statistically totally reversed. But, in fact, this was only the result of a process begun in 1914. The relative importance of the trade of third world countries during the inter-war period is mainly due to the dizzying fall of trade among the industrialised countries.
The 1914 war, in signalling the end of world capitalism's era of imperialist expansion, marked the beginning of a process of rapid shrinking of markets outside the capitalist system.
It is estimated that the proportion of the world population engaged in capitalist production was 10 per cent in 1850. This proportion reached nearly 30 per cent in 1914. But since the beginning of this century this expansion has greatly declined in the industrialised countries. The number of German workers rose from 8 million in 1882 to 14 million in 1925, but their proportion in the working population, after having reached 50 per cent in 1895, fell to 45 per cent in 1925. [1] [22] "What was true of Germany was also true on an international scale. The working class percentage stabilised itself at round about 50 per cent; in England it was rather more, in France and Germany rather less." [2] [23] This marked decline in the expansion of the 'principal productive force' continues up to the present time.In the most industrialised countries of the world, the proportion of "industrial workers, including construction workers", according to INSEE [3] [24], in 1968 was only 47-48 per cent for Germany and England, 45 per cent for the whole of the European Economic Community, 35 per cent for the United States, USSR and Japan. These figures should be relatively higher since they exclude workers engaged in transportation, agriculture and fishing. But they undoubtedly prove that the rate of expansion of the working class has greatly declined since the end of the ascendant phase of the system after 1914.
In the underdeveloped countries this decline is even more pronounced. From 1950 to 1960 in Asia, Africa and Latin America, the number of new wage earners in every hundred inhabitants was 9 times lower than in the developed countries.Until 1914, the population effectively integrated into the capitalist economy grew faster than the world population. That was during the ascendant phase of capitalism. This tendency has, since then, been definitively reversed.
Growth since World War 2
There was, therefore, a profound change in capitalism after 1914 and especially after 1929. Without doubt, the fundamental characteristic of this change is the end of imperialist expansion. Imperialism was, in effect, the principal outlet for 'ascendant' capitalism. This outlet absorbed the relatively small part of capitalist production, the surplus value destined to be reinvested, the realisation of which is indispensable for capital accumulation. We need only observe the radical upheaval which accompanied the end of imperialist expansion: two world wars and a crisis as profound as the one in 1929-38 in less than thirty years.
The period which World War 2 initiated cannot be situated outside the framework of the conditions which existed in 1914. As we have seen, colonial, or semi-colonial, markets greatly declined in importance during this period.
Many have considered this phase of expansion to be quite different from the period of quasi-stagnation in the 30s. The Trotskyists of the '4th International' have even used the pompous term, 'Neo-Capitalism', to characterise and thus indicate the importance they attach to the change in the economy.
In a few instances, growth rates since World War 2 have caught up with or even surpassed those attained during the ascendant phase of capitalism before 1913. This is the case for countries such as France or Japan. It is, however, far from being the case for the greatest industrial power, the United States (with 50 per cent of world production at the beginning of the 50s, [4] [25] a 4.6 per cent average annual rate of growth between 1957 and 1965 as opposed to 6.9 per cent between 1850 and 1880 [5] [26]. But the real nature of this growth is radically different from the expansion which was completed by 1913.
The principal fields of economic expansion since World War 2 have been: post-war reconstruction; permanent and massive armaments production; and better exploitation of old markets.
Only the 'better exploitation of old markets' is common to the two periods, but is is not a new development in the history of capitalism. Thus we should consider the major importance that this policy has acquired in the epoch when the discovery of really new markets is impossible.
Even though the third world markets have lost importance due to their insufficiency, their exploitation has, nonetheless, been continued as effectively as possible. Likewise, those powers still possessing internal 'extra-capitalist' markets (in particular, a still backward agriculture as in Japan, France and Italy) have proceeded to systematically integrate them since the war. But unlike the nineteenth century, this type of outlet had become much too limited for the needs of the 'natural' expansion of capitalism. It is like the life cycle of the water-lily whose size doubles each day : while it may have required a relatively long time to start growing and to eventually cover half of the pool, it needs only one more day to reach, in a single spurt of growth, the outer limits of its field of expansion. Each day's growth requires the area of the pool to be double what it was the day before. But since the total surface of the pool is limited in advance, the area which remains diminishes at the same rate as its needs of expansion increase.
At the beginning of the century, the mass of outlets which capitalism needed to assure one year of growth was more than six times less than that which is necessary for a year's production today. This ratio would be even larger if capitalism had had the same ability to expand after 1913 as before. But simultaneously, with the greater demand for new markets, the external outlets have contracted rapidly. Because of this, capitalism has had to resort to the palliatives of destruction and arms production to try to compensate for rapid losses in 'living space'.
A 'reconstruction economy' never appeared during ascendant capitalism. The inter-imperialist conflicts of that phase had nothing in common with the wars of the twentieth century. Those efforts of destruction never touched the centres of production. There was no 'reconstruction' because there was no real destruction. As for the production of armaments and military costs, their volume as well as their proportion of the national product of the great powers in the nineteenth century can hardly be compared with what they have become under modern capitalism.
"Hohenzollern Germany was regarded as definitely militaristic, and in the years which immediately preceded the first world war she greatly increased her military budget, which reached its culminating point in peace-time with what was then (1913) the huge sum of £100 million , inclusive of naval expenditure. But even then it represented only rather less than 4 per cent of the total national income which was then no less than £2,500 million." (Our emphasis). [6] [27]
There is no possible comparison with the 10 per cent of the GNP devoted to military expenditures currently reached and often surpassed by the United States since the era of 'peace' after Word War 2, nor with the 20 per cent for the USSR.
Capitalism in the last decades, far from constituting a renewal of the ascendant phase which ended in 1913, appears instead to be the logical 'synthetic' outcome of the thirty years of decline which preceded it.
In effect, capitalism 'discovered' during these years of stagnation the economic 'benefits' of reconstruction and production for destruction.
The self-destruction of Europe during World War I was accompanied by a 15 per cent growth in American production. Amid the chaos of the old continent, the United States discovered an important outlet; Europe had to import masses of consumer goods, means of production and arms from America. Once the war ended, the reconstruction of Europe proved to be the new and important outlet. Through massive destruction with an eye to reconstruction, capitalism has discovered a way out, dangerous and temporary but effective, for its new problems of finding outlets.
During the first war, the amount of destruction was not 'sufficient'; military operations only directly affected an industrial sector representing less than one-tenth of world production (around 5-7 per cent) [1] [34]. In 1929, world capitalism again ran into a crisis situation.
As if the lesson had been well-learned the amount of destruction accomplished in World War 2 was far more intense and extensive. "All in all therefore during the second world war almost a third of the total industrial sector of the world was drawn into the direct arena of military action." [2] [35]
Russia, Germany, Japan, Great-Britain, France and Belgium violently suffered the effects of a war which for the first time had the conscious aim of systematically destroying the existing industrial potential. The 'prosperity' of Europe and Japan after the war seemed already foreseen by the end of the war, (Marshall Plan, etc...).
Contrary to common opinion, 'reconstruction' does not stop when the ruined nation regains its pre-war levels of production: reconstruction does not only involve the directly productive goods but also all the infra-structures and means of life destroyed during the war, even though their reconstruction is not immediately necessary in order to attain pre-war production levels. Reconstruction is never undertaken with pre-war technology; important progress in productivity and the concentration of capital has occurred during the war. Also, the fact that the former levels of production are regained does not necessarily mean that the same mass of value will again be tied up in productive capital. Finally, during their destruction those countries concerned became industrially backward in relation to the other powers. Their reconstruction cannot be considered completed until the moment when they regain not their former levels o production, but ones which make them again internationally competitive.
In this sense, reconstruction characterised the growth of the post-World War 2 period right up to the 1960s and not just to the 1950s as is often supposed.
If we remember that the percentage of the American national revenue destined for military purposes was less than 1 per cent in 1929 and that before 1913 the 4 per cent reached by Germany on the eve of the war represented an unprecedented maximum, we will understand the significance of the per centages maintained after 1945.
[2] [54] Claude, p.70
[3] [55] League of Nations, ‘Apercu General Du Commerce Mondial' 1938, cited by Henri Claude, p.30
[4] [56] Claude, p.24
[6] [58] Sternberg, p.494
[7] [59] For example, in 1962 American military expenditure in planes, missiles, electronic and telecommunications equipment accounted for 75 per cent of the total military expenses of the country. Ships, artillery, vehicles and related equipment which were once the mainstay of the armed forces, made up the remaining 25 per cent.
*sv¼v is the definition of the rate of exploitation (or the rate of surplus value).
[10] [62] Claude, p.61
[11] [63] In 1945, there was so much progress in capital concentration in the United States that it has been estimated (Fritz Sternberg) that the 250 largest enterprises produced the equivalent of what some 75,000 industries produced before the conflict.
[12] [64] Speech of May 28, 1941
[13] [65] 9,480,000 unemployed in 1939, 670,000 in 1944, 3,395,000 in 1949 (President's Economic Report, 1950)
[14] [66] United Nations, 26th Session of the General Assembly, United States response to the UN questionnaire on ‘The Economic and Social Consequences of the Arms Race...' 1972, p.48
The accelerating of the rhythm of development of the productive forces after World War 2 was one of the factors which provoked the split in the '4th International' in 1952. According to the 'Lambertist' faction of the AJS-OCI (The Organisation Communiste Internationaliste is the French Trotskyist group headed by Lambert, formerly linked to the Healyite Socialist Labour League in the UK (now the Workers Revolutionary Party) and the Wolforthite Workers League in the US. The AJS (Alliance de Jeunesse Socialiste, is the youth section of the OCI), the economic premise underlying the possibility of, and necessity for, socialist revolution is the total cessation of the growth of the productive forces. The Lambertists are, in this respect, faithful to the letter to the transitional programme of Trotsky. We have seen at the beginning of this article, the inconsistency of this theory from the marxist point of view.Growth statistics for the period of reconstruction render this theory absurd. In order to bring the statistics into line with their views, the Lambertists insist on the unproductive nature of armaments production. But even if one is certain that arms production acts as a brake on real production, it is statistically impossible to pretend that it has paralysed or 'nullified' the growth of the productive forces since 1945.The stubborn, short-sighted dogmatism of this position is all the more ridiculous in that it violently clashes with another dogma (the transitional programme) so dear to the AJS-OCI: "The USSR is not capitalist, it is a degenerated workers‘ state." Productive forces could thus develop there much more rapidly than in the United States. But Russia devotes a much greater part of its production to armaments than have the greatest Western powers.For the Trotskyists of the official 4th International, (Ligue Communiste -Mandel, defunct), decadence is not defined by the 'clogging' of the growth of the productive forces, but by the slowing down of this growth under the weight of the relations of production. In that they are faithful 'to the letter' to Marx. But if one scratches just a little below the surface, one discovers a patchwork of dogmas as contradictory as those of the AJS.In a pamphlet entitled, "Qu'est-ce-que l'AJS?", Weber, the theoretician of the 4th International, tried to criticise the "absurd theories and grotesque contortions of the Lambertists" on this question [1] [68]. In order to resolve the contradictions apparent in the dogma of the 'degenerated workers' state', (Mandel and Co also believe that there are a lot of countries in the world which are non-capitalist), Weber attributes a productive character to armaments production. To answer the problem of Trotsky's formulation that the premises of socialism are dependent on the arrested growth of productive forces, Weber explains that Trotsky only 'described the reality which was before his eyes in 1938'.As for the problem of defining the characteristics or the content of the slow-down which defines the periods of decadence, the Trotskyists no longer give us anything very concrete to go on. They talk about 'neo-capitalism' which supposedly began right after World War 2 and which is characterised by an "unprecedented economic expansion". They tell us that "the general crisis of capitalism was brought about by the first war"; but they also tell us that it was in 1848, 120 years ago, that Marx denounced the capitalist production as fetters on the development of the productive forces; it was in 1848 that he declared the capitalist mode of production to be "regressive and reactionary" [2] [69]. And they remind us about the sentences in the Communist Manifesto:"For many a decade past the history of industry and commerce is but the history of the revolt of modern productive forces against modern conditions of production...And here it becomes evident, that the bourgeoisie is unfit any longer to be the ruling class in society, and to impose its conditions of existence upon society as an over-riding law". This selection is cited by Weber in order to pose the question, "Is this to say that Marx and Engels were mistaken?" Weber argues that the reply to this question which every Lambertist must unhesitatingly agree to if he takes the Lambertist theses at all seriously, is the following. "If the contradiction between the development of productive forces and the continuation of the capitalist relations of production is expressed purely and simply in terms of the blockage of the productive forces, then Marx and Engels were wrong, not only in 1848 but all their lives, since according to the Lambertist position, the stagnation of the productive forces began in 1914!" More confusion follows: "But the Lambertists theory of a 'clogging' of the productive forces is foreign to marxism..."On the other hand, if you believe that Weber, Marx and Engels are not wrong, then after the infallibility of Trotsky, the infallibility of Marx and Engels is also saved, in Weber's head at least, and the dogma of these different infallibilities is respected. But suddenly you find yourself entangled in the following notions: the decadence of capitalism was under full sway in 1848; the beginning of "the general crisis of capitalism" only in 1914; and the height of the victorious expansion of "neo-capitalism" in 1960! Is the rupture in capitalist development to be situated in the "decades before 1848", "120 years ago" in 1848, or in 1914, or even in 1945 at the beginning of the so-called "neo-capitalism"? When does this famous "epoch of social revolution" of which Marx spoke begin?It would be difficult to piece together any coherent findings in this lamentable theoretical patchwork which was, in any case, elaborated only to salvage a few official Trotskyist dogmas and to justify the 'progressive character' of all bureaucratic movements in the third world, the 'anti-imperialist' nature of Peking and Moscow, and all sorts of opportunisms involving trade unions ('critical' support), elections ('pedagogical' benefits), and reforms ('transitional movements towards socialism'). But in the last analysis, for the Leninists of What Is To Be Done?, all these economic problems of characterising historical periods, etc... are unimportant because these 'scientists' are convinced that the only real problem is revolutionary leadership: "The present crisis in human culture is the crisis in the proletarian leadership." (Trotsky, 1938)There is little to be learned from this theoretical patchwork quilt (which actually serves only as a cloak with which to cover the various types of Trotskyist opportunism), except to realise the necessity of developing a serious definition of what is signified by the slackening in the growth of the productive forces.As we said at the beginning of this article, a period of decadence is expressed by a slackening or slowing down in the growth of the productive forces when:1) such a lack of growth specifically results from the constraints imposed by the relations of production;2) the process is inevitable and irreversible;3) an ever widening gap is created between the actual development of the productive forces and what would have been possible had the fetters constituted by the dominant relations of production been absent.When Marx and Engels wrote the Communist Manifesto, there were periodic slow-downs in growth caused by cyclical crises. During these crises, the fundamental contradictions of capitalism were clearly projected. But these "revolts of the modern forces of production against the modern relations of production" were only the revolts of capitalism's youth. The outcome of these regular explosions was only the strengthening of the system which, during the course of his dramatic ascension, had thrown off its infantile habits along with the last feudal constraints standing in its way. In 1850, only 10 per cent of the world population was integrated into the capitalist relations of production. The wage system had its whole future before it. Marx and Engels had the genius to extract from the crises of capitalism's ascendancy the essence of all crises to come. In so doing, they revealed to future generations the bases of capitalism's most profound convulsions. They were able to do so because from its beginning a social form carries inside itself the seeds of all the contradictions which will carry it to its death. But insofar as these contradictions are not developed to the point of permanently hindering the economic growth, they constitute the very motor of this growth. The slow-downs which the capitalist economy of the nineteenth century joltingly experienced have nothing to do with its permanent and growing fetters. On the contrary, the intensity of these crises was softened by their repetition. Marx and Engels were completely mistaken in their analysis of 1848. (Marx in Class struggles in France as well as Engels in his later introduction to this text, were moreover not afraid to recognise this). Much more lucid was Rosa Luxemburg's analysis in 1898: "If one looks more closely at the different causes of all previous great international crises, one will be convinced that they are all not the expression of the weakness of old age of the capitalist economy but rather of its childhood. We still have not progressed to that degree of development and exhaustion which would produce the fatal, periodic collision of the forces of production with the limits of the market, which is the actual capitalist crisis of old age....If the world market has now more or less filled out, and can no longer be enlarged by sudden extensions; and if, at the same time, the productivity of labour strides relentlessly forward, then in less or more time the periodic conflict of the forces of production with the limits of exchanges will begin, and will repeat itself more sharply and more stormily." (Rosa Luxemburg, Reform or revolution )When the period of post-World War 2 reconstruction opened, a long time had already elapsed since capitalism could "no longer be enlarged by sudden extensions". For decades, the productivity of labour had risen too quickly to be contained within the capitalist relations of production. For thirty years already, repeated and increasingly violent assaults of the forces of production against the barriers which block their development have brutally ravaged the entire society.Only the misery and the barbarism of these years of growing depression can account for the general bewilderment provoked by the economic development which began with reconstruction. For, however one envisages it, this 'development' constitutes in fact the greatest slackening in the growth of the productive forces that humanity has ever known. Never before has the contrast between what is possible and what is actually accomplished reached such proportions. Never "has the continuation of development appeared so much like a decline". (Marx).In order to appreciate the magnitude of this decline many questions might be asked. Should armaments production be included or not in the volume of production effectively realised in order to determine the development of the productive forces? How can we determine the level of production 'which would have been possible'? Must we compare the levels effectively realised with those which would have been reached if economic growth continued to follow the rates achieved during the system's ascendant phase? And, in that case, should we begin from 1913 or 1945? Or should we determine the rates which would have been possible given the existing technology of that time? Is it necessary to consider whether the productive forces 'left on their own' would have developed according to rates which were increasing or which remained constant?
In order to answer these questions we are going to compare the world's industrial production as it developed from 1913 to 1959 (including armaments production) with what would have taken place if industrial growth had continued after 1913 along the same rates attained during the decade 1880-1890. [3] [70] (We will assume a constant rate of development. In reality, this rate would tend to increase under the influence of rising productivity). We are particularly interested in the period which began right after World War 2. The comparison with the hypothetical growth defined in the first example (above) will be completed by a second comparison with another example of hypothetical growth based on new growth rates made possible by the development of technology at the time of World War 2. In order to get a more precise idea of the extent of the decline we will start this hypothetical growth from the end of the war in 1946. For this comparison we have chosen as the growth rate which would have been attainable following World War 2 (if the capitalist relations of production had not hindered development), the rate which was reached by the United States industrial production between 1939 and 1944. The war had opened up important outlets for the American economy and thus enabled the productive apparatus to operate at its maximum strength. However, this rate is limited by the fact that such an immense growth in output involved a type of production which could not be reintegrated into production in order to accelerate, in its turn, further growth; namely, armaments. Moreover, this rate was realised in the United States at the same time that the other powers were war-torn: American economic growth, therefore, could not profit from technological development furnished by international collaboration. We are keeping this rate of growth nevertheless, because it has the virtue of having been actually attained at a given time and thus gives us an appreciation of society's actual technological capacities. The index of United States industrial production went from 109 to 235 between 1939 and 1944 ( 100=1938 ) which is a rate of growth of 110 per cent in five years, (see graph).
On the graph we can see the divergences which, in both cases, widen with growing rapidity. We can see, even more clearly, the magnitude of these slow-downs by recording their progression on a separate graph. (The first graph is scaled in semi-logarithms so the progression of the divergences is poorly shown.)
These graphs are only very approximate and give a picture which is probably an under-estimation of the actual extent of the brake on the rate of growth. However, they do give a clear idea of the unprecedented effectiveness of this brake, of its irreversible and inevitable character, as well as its uninterrupted increase. The periods during which the gaps are narrowed correspond to the periods of rearmament or reconstruction. Here their function as temporary palliatives clearly stands out.After the slowing down of the growth of productive forces, it is necessary to see whether capitalism after 1914 and especially after 1945 has been condemned to deeper and more widespread crises (the second characteristic of a society's economic decadence). This will lead us to examine the problem of the nature of armaments productions and its limitations. We will first consider the period 1914-46, followed by the period extending from the end of World War 2 to the present.
[1] [71] ‘Qu' est-ce que l ‘AJS', Cahiers rouge, series ‘Marx ou creve' (sic), pp. 13-35
[2] [72] Ibid, p. 30
[3] [73] From 1880 to 1890, the index of industrial production multiplied by 1.6, Sternberg, p.21
Such an overview necessarily demands an analysis of military production and thus of the more general problem of non-productive labour.
The panorama of crises presented by capitalism during the period 1914-46 requires no commentary: two world wars and a depression on the scale of 1929, in less than thirty years, speak eloquently enough. Two remarks may, nonetheless, be of use. Because it was an economic crisis in the most traditional meaning of the term, the depression of 1929-34 is often cited as the crisis of modern capitalism. But the two world wars also constituted crises of the system in no way less profound. In the same way as the economic depression of the inter-war period, the world conflicts expressed in the most brutal fashion the incapacity of capitalist relations of production to continue to reproduce themselves in the normal way. 'Pure' economic crises eliminate excess capital through bankruptcy; war achieves the same end through physical destruction and armed violence. But in both cases, the content is the same: capital is forced to destroy itself under the pressure of the contradictions of its own mode of functioning. In both cases, the system gives rise to violent convulsions provoked by the definitive inability of the dominant relations of production to adapt to the needs and potentialities of society. In a world dominated by capital, there is nothing which is not economic: these 'international political crises' called world wars, far from being extra-economic phenomena, have only been the barbarous manifestation of the most profound economic crises.
Unlike the crises of the ascendant phase of capitalism, the convulsions of decadent capitalism bring to the fore a general and accentuated movement of systematic deterioration. In this very fact lies the proof of their different nature. The crisis of 1929 brought about a fall in production greater than that caused by World War I. World War 2 was far more destructive than World War I, and was a disaster incomparably greater than that of 1929. This progression in intensity indicates the irreversible character of a general movement of decline.
From 1914 until the end of World War 2 the importance and meaning of these convulsions became more and more obvious. But the absence of serious crises during the twenty years following World War 2 was enough to convince commentators of the definitive disappearance of crises within capitalism, and consequently to relegate the crises of the preceding period to the never-never land of "crises of growth".
And yet, in the period immediately after World War 2, capitalism began a new cycle on foundations which were no more sound than those which had precipitated the war. Economic expansion depended more than ever on two crutches which had just demonstrated their inherent weaknesses in terms of any long-term solution to the crisis. These crutches were the mechanisms of "reconstruction" and production for military ends.
Of course, the destruction was far more extensive this time, and the reconstruction would last longer than it did after World War I. War became permanent through constantly maintained local conflicts, and the production of war material achieved higher levels in "peace time" than during the two world conflagrations. The state learned better how to handle the effects of internal contradictions which progressively undermine the system, and tended to emerge more and more as the system's controlling force. In short, capital had begun a new phase of its decline with an array of particularly effective palliatives, but the purely palliative nature of these measures has never been concealed for a moment.
This point has been dealt with at length in the article "La crise", which appeared in Révolution Internationale (old series) nos. 6 and 7, and we will not repeat it here. Rather we will content ourselves with a review of some of the principal economic phenomena which, since the second half of the 60s, unequivocally demonstrate the limits of these palliatives.
The completion of the reconstruction of the European countries, and of Japan, around 1965 gave rise to profound dislocation in the international economic channels which had presided over capitalist "expansion" since the war. All the international exchange mechanisms entered into crisis. The former outlets for American industry suddenly began to display a rude, commercial aggression. In 1967 the United States recorded its first balance of trade deficit since 1893. In short, what had for decades propped up the system was now itself exhausted, and with no possible remedy anywhere in sight. The cycle whereby capitalism had "developed" since the beginning of its decline (crisis - war - reconstruction), had once again arrived at a fatal turning point: the end of reconstruction.
The limits of the economic stimulus of military production
We saw in the previous sections the "virtues" of the outlet constituted by military needs and the importance of this factor in the capitalist economy since World War 2. The limits of this kind of outlet, universally recognised as one of the major "underpinnings of capitalist expansion" in our era, must be analysed if one wishes to understand the basis for the inevitability of the system's next major crisis. We dwell at length on this subject not only because it forms part of the answer to the problem of crises during the decadence of capitalism, but also because it is one of the most spectacular illustrations of a particularly significant phenomenon of this decadence: the precipitous development of non-productive sectors at the expense of the productive sector.
The general confusion which prevails with regard to military production is not foreign to our attempt to clarify the problem: it is indeed not rare to hear "marxists" claim that any distinction between production such as that of armaments and the means of production or means of subsistence corresponds to "ethical criteria" completely foreign to marxist economic criteria [1] [74].
Armaments: a pure loss for global capital
Capital lives only for and by its self-expansion, that is to say from that process which begins with the exploitation of living labour - the extraction of surplus value - and concludes with the increase of capital due to the transformation of a part of this surplus value into new capital.
Capital is not synonymous with accumulated wealth - even if it is also that. Its specific characteristic lies in its capacity to extract surplus labour and in the goal of this exploitation: the growth of capital. Capital is first and foremost a social relationship.
But armaments have the unique characteristic of possessing a use value which does not allow them to enter, in any form, into the process of production. A washing machine can contribute to the reproduction of labour power, just like a loaf of bread or a shirt. Through the content of their use value, these goods can serve as capital in the form of variable capital. A computer, a ton of iron, or a steam engine, insofar as they are means or objects of labour can function as capital in the form of constant capital. But arms can only destroy or rust (we are discounting for the moment the indirect productive effect of arms production - cf the second part of this article).
Obviously, arms can furnish capital by metabolism. Once sold, they are transformed into money, and with the sum obtained, the capitalist who sold them can buy means of production or subsistence. But the arms themselves do not become capital, for all that. The buyer of arms pays with capital and receives in exchange a product which can never become capital. What global capital earns in the person of the seller of arms is lost in the person of their purchaser. The global result of the operation is zero.
Let us take as an example Marcel Dassault, one of the world's leading arms manufacturers, who sells arms to foreign countries and also to the French state. Consider an example of the first type of sale: Mirage jets sold to Peru. Dassault receives in payment a sum of money, which he can use to replace the capital expended and to increase the capital of his enterprise through the purchase of new machines and new quantities of labour power. For that faction of capital represented by Dassault the exchange is a normal and productive affair. For French capital, the same holds true.
What does this exchange represent, however, for Peruvian capital? To get the necessary money for the purchase of these Mirages, Peru must, for example, sell an equivalent quantity of fish-meal. It could have used this value to increase its own power of exploitation, its capital (fish-meal factories, or fishing boats). Instead, Peru has transformed that value into supersonic fighter-bombers. Such bombers might inflate the pride of the "progressive" military clique in power, but the national capital will never be able to use them directly to extract a penny of surplus value (short of establishing a civil transport service of limited profitability). For Peruvian capital, then, this operation is paid for by a destruction of capital.
For world capital, the unproductive nature of armaments has not disappeared: it has simply been displaced from one point to another within its own sphere. Whatever the exchanges that have taken place, the fact remains that somewhere in the world productive labour has been sterilised as far as the development of capital goes. The place where the weight of that unproductive activity makes itself felt changes nothing about the problem; it is not because armaments cross a national border that their nature in relation to global capital has been transformed.
Now consider the second case: Dassault sells his Mirages to the French state. For the seller of armaments, the operation is still just as profitable and productive for his capital. But for French capital as a whole, it no longer is. Whether through indirect taxes, taxes on capital or taxes on labour, it is always surplus value extracted from living labour that the state, Dassault's customer, uses to buy the Mirages. For the national capital, it is a question of wasted surplus value.
Therefore, each time that the national capital sacrifices, through this waste of surplus value, a certain amount of labour for the production of arms consumed by the state, there is that much more surplus value which will be unproductively consumed and which will not expand at all the value of capital as a whole.It is common to counter this analysis with the idea that the concept of global capital is a pure abstraction, without any real existence, which cannot be used in an argument concerning the problem of the profitability of any kind of production. According to this argument, each capitalist or each nation worries very little about ‘global capital'. It would therefore be absurd to attempt to define an economic totality on the basis of a sum of antagonistic entities.
The fact that capital, as a global phenomenon, lives only in a divided form does not imply that it does not exist at the global level. The totality of the thieves in one city live in constant competition with each other and the law of their environment is none other than that of the strongest thief. This in no way changes the fact that this totality exists in itself, and that it has its own interests (to extend the example, with regard to the police). The fact that it cannot exist for itself, that is with a collective and unified consciousness of its interests and acting in relation to those interests in no way changes the problem. Global capital is always a sum of antagonistic capitals. But it exists nonetheless with general laws which act exclusively at its own level, with its own phenomena (world war, world crises) which impose themselves on each of its fractions and over which no fraction of capital has a real control.
Under capitalism the domination of capital extended itself to the whole of the planet a long time age. Every commodity today contains labour and primary materials from every corner of the world. In such a state of affairs, it is first of all the reality of global capital which determines the reality of each of its parts, and not the other way around.
Massive military production is a phenomenon which, because of its origin, its development and its effects, concerns the world capitalist economy. To attempt to judge its nature outside the concept of global capital is quite simply a renunciation of any analysis.
In order to analyse the problem of the reproduction of capital, Marx does not hesitate to put himself on this terrain:
"In order to examine the object of our investigation in its integrity, free from all disturbing secondary circumstances, we must treat the whole world as one nation and assume that capitalist production is everywhere established and has possessed itself of every branch of the economy." (Marx, Capital, Book 1, p.581, London 1970)
This has nothing to do with any so-called theory of ultra-imperialism. It is a definition of the only objective terrain on which the fundamental phenomena of developed capitalism can be understood.
Certain individuals nonetheless accept the concept of global capital (a concept which can be applied both at the world level and at the level of national capital), without accepting the possibility of production which is simultaneously profitable for one capitalist or a fraction of global capital but not profitable for global capital as a whole. This is an objection which might be encapsulated by the American witticism: ‘What's good for General Motors is good for the United States'. It is thus imagined that if military production is productive for one capitalist, it is also productive for global capital.
Just as in the case of the first objection, here again the contradictory reality of capital is being ignored. The fundamental contradiction of the capitalist system, that which underlies all its contradictions, is that which opposes the ever-increasingly universal, socialised character of the production process, to its private, fragmented, property relations, on the basis of which the process takes place. In the first example, only the fragmented, divided aspect of capital is taken into consideration, while the global nature of capital is ignored. In this case, it is the inevitable antagonisms between capitals which is shunted aside, giving way to a harmonious vision of global capital without contradictions between its parts or between its parts and the whole. The conditions in which a particular capitalist realises his profits is obviously tied in the long run to those of capital as a whole. But things can develop in such a way that this tie becomes temporarily attenuated, to the point of making ‘what is bad' for the United States appear as ‘what is good for General Motors'! ( The classic example is that of the capitalist who produces consumer goods necessary for the working class: each general wage increase is for him, a supplementary condition for the realisation of a market, whereas it constitutes a threat to the rate of profit of capital as a whole.)
The inevitable disharmony which reigns in the private property system can only increase with the decline of the system. Thus, this phase gives rise to the development of state intervention with the aim of containing, through forced centralisation, the ever-increasing tendencies of disintegration.
There is then nothing surprising in the fact that the same criterion of profitability in the capitalist system gives different results when it is applied to a particular capitalist than when it is applied to global capital.
We must therefore explain why and how it is that the state, as the representative of national capital, maintains the capitalist sellers of armaments, while the production of armaments is ‘unproductive' for the national capital (leaving aside for the moment the possibility of transferring the costs to another state). And, first of all, it is necessary to define in a precise manner the marxist criterion of ‘productive' and ‘unproductive' labour.
Marx's answer can be summarised by the famous formula: "Labour which directly creates surplus value, that is to say, which expands capital, is productive." [1] [76]
This formulation is specific to the capitalist mode of production. It is distinct from that which applies to ‘the question of productive labour in general', when we study: "the labour process under its most simple aspect, common to all its historical forms, as a process between man and nature." [2] [77]
From this general viewpoint, historically, all labour is productive from the moment that it ends up in a product and that product corresponds to any human need. "In the labour process, therefore, man's activity, with the help of the instruments of labour, effects an alteration, designed from the commencement, in the material worked upon. This process disappears in the product; the latter is a use-value, nature's material adapted by a change of form to the wants of man. Labour has incorporated itself with its subject: the former is materialised, the latter transformed. That which in the labourer appeared as movement, now appears in the product as a fixed quality without motion. The blacksmith forges and the product is forging.
If we examine the whole process from the point of view of its result, the product, it is plain that both the instruments and the subject of labour, are means of production, and that the labour itself is productive labour." [3] [78]
Marx further explains: "This method of determining, from the standpoint of the labour-process alone, what is productive labour, is by no means directly applicable to the case of the capitalist process of production". (Marx, Ibid)
The productive process takes on, under capitalism, specific forms which no longer permit us to content ourselves with this first, almost tautological formulation. There are two reasons for this. The first appears when we look at capital from the viewpoint of labour. In capitalism, labour power is purchased by capital, of which it seems to become an integral part. This labour power can affirm its productive capacity only by restoring to capital a sum of value higher than which it receives from capital (wages). In order to be productive as living labour and not as mere part of capital, it is no longer sufficient for labour to produce any random value in any random quantity: it must create a ‘super value', a surplus value. The second reason becomes obvious if we look at living labour from the viewpoint of capital. The goal of capital is not to satisfy needs, but to produce profit, surplus value. This does not eliminate the first determination of productive labour, to the extent that capitalism produces commodities and therefore use values. But this determination becomes ‘insufficient'. Use value is no longer, as it was in previous systems, the basis of production; it remains only as something which must be tolerated, a necessary support for exchange value, but whose specific content is of no importance to the capitalist.
Thus, it is not sufficient, for the individual capitalist, for the labour he buys to concretise itself in any particular use value: that labour must expand his capital.
"Surplus value, the specific product of the capitalist process of production, is only created as a result of the exchange with productive labour. What constitutes its specific use-value for capital is not its particular useful character, any more than the particular useful qualities of the product in which it is materialised, but its character as the element which creates exchange-value (surplus value)." [4] [79]
"That labour alone is productive whose process is the same as the productive process of the consumption of labour power by capital or the capitalist." [5] [80]
In short, the way of determining productive labour under capitalism differs from the general determination which held true for previous systems by virtue of the difference which capitalism introduces at the level of ‘the productive process of the consumption of labour power'.
This difference does not reside in the actual extraction of surplus labour: the feudal lord or the slave owner of antiquity also disposed of the surplus labour of their serfs and slaves. What distinguishes surplus value from other forms of surplus labour is the fact that it is transformed into new capital and not consumed in a non-productive way as in antiquity or feudalism. It is only when this transformation of surplus value is completed that the expansion of capital has been achieved (the accumulation of capital). The problem of the possibility of this transformation is thus fundamental in the definition of productive labour in the capitalist system.
"The distinction between productive labour and unproductive labour is important with respect to accumulation, because the exchange against productive labour alone is one of the conditions for the reconversion of surplus-value into capital." [6] [81]
But it is at this level that most of the confusion about the problem of productive labour arises. In effect, the conditions for the transformation of surplus value differ depending on whether they involve the individual capitalist or global capital.
A capitalist consumes what his own enterprise produces only in exceptional cases. Each fraction of capital is only an atom within a network whose complexity increases at the same rate as the socialisation of production. Each capitalist has only the most fragmented consciousness of this network and has practically no control over it. Once a commodity has been produced, it plunges into commercial circuits and disappears from the sphere of the capitalist who produced it. What is important for the capitalist is to receive the monetary counterpart of the commodity which will permit him, in turn, to take from the productive circuit the goods necessary for the reconstitution and expansion of his capital.
It follows that for the individual capitalist, or in a more general way, a fraction of global capital, "... the fact that labour is productive has absolutely nothing to do with the determinant content of the labour, its particular utility or the particular use-value in which it is materialised". [7] [82]
Whatever the use value of his product might be, from the moment that he succeeds in realising their exchange value, his surplus value can be transformed into capital, the determination of productive labour is independent of the content of that labour.
Global capital, on the other hand, itself consumes the essential part of its product since it is constituted by all the capitalists. The use value content of what it produces directly conditions its possibilities of expansion and realisation.
"To accumulate it is necessary to convert a portion of the surplus-product into capital. But we cannot except by a miracle, convert into capital anything but such articles as can be employed in the labour-process (ie. means of production), and such further articles as are suitable for the sustenance of the labourer (ie. means of subsistence). Consequently, a part of surplus-value must have been applied to the production of additional means of production and subsistence, over and above the quantity of those things required to replace the capital advanced. In one word, surplus-value is convertible into capital solely because the surplus-product, whose value it is, already comprises the material elements of new capital." [8] [83]
From the viewpoint of global capital, the process of the general accumulation of capital - and this is the only point of view which can be taken into consideration when it is a question of judging the capitalist system - productive labour is that which creates surplus value and which is crystallised in use values which themselves can be productively consumed in the process of capital accumulation.
This why we assert that labour (living and dead) which goes into the production of goods such as arms (as well as luxury goods,etc) constitutes unproductive labour.
"The services that the capitalist buys voluntarily or involuntarily (through the state, etc) for his consumption because of their use-value, do not become factors of capital, any more than the commodities bought for his private consumption. Consequently, these do not constitute productive labour and their agents are not productive labourers." [9] [84]
Most of the confusion amongst marxists on the question of productive labour has two sources.
The first is that Marx mainly dealt with the problem from the viewpoint of the individual capitalist, or from the viewpoint of the worker as someone exploited by capital. Two reasons can explain Marx's insistence on this single aspect of the problem: the polemic he launched against J.B. Say and Bastiat, who located the problem on this terrain, and the relatively secondary importance of this problem in the course of the general development of capitalism at the time that Marx was writing. (Unproductive expenditures of capital took on really significant proportions only with the period begun by World War 1.) [10] [85]
The second source of confusion perhaps resides in the meaning of the term ‘surplus value'. Let us imagine a capitalist nation which in the course of a year produces only goods and services whose consumption is directly productive, that is to say, commodities entering directly into the productive process. (We therefore assume that, for example, there is no production of armaments or luxury goods.) At the end of the first year, the capitalists find themselves in possession of a mass of products which they dispose of to the exclusion of the rest of society: this is the mass of surplus value, the real surplus value of the global capital of the nation.
Let us further assume that at the end of this first year, they decide not to devote, as they have been doing up until then, all the extracted surplus value in the production of new productive goods. In keeping with their privileged situation, they agree to create luxury industries: in order to defend themselves from possible aggression from other nations, they decide to create a military industry. These two new industries are obviously going to function according to capitalist relations of production: wage labour, etc...[11] [86]
The problem is the following: what is the nature and origin of the profit which the capitalists of these new sectors are going to collect? Do the workers in these industries create surplus value? What is the relationship between the profit of the capitalists in this sector and the real surplus value of the productive sector?
The answer appears clearly as soon as one realises that all the production of these sectors is bought by capitalists, by the capitalist class as a whole (through their state apparatus in the case of military goods). The wages of the workers in these industries, as well as the profits of the corresponding capitalists, are paid for by previously created surplus value. Global capital is not going to be expanded by a single hour of the labour provided by these non-productive industries. It is, on the other hand, going to devote a part of surplus value which could have been devoted to its self-expansion to the maintenance of both the workers and the capitalists of these branches.
From the viewpoint of global capital - or national, in this case - these workers do not create surplus value. On the contrary, they consume it. But from the viewpoint of the capitalist in the sectors in question, these workers give them through their surplus labour, the right to dispose (at a rate determined in relation to the capital they have invested, according to the law of the ‘capitalist environment') of a certain portion of the mass of real surplus value.
Dassault or Chanel provide other capitalists with commodities produced according to the capitalist mode of exploitation: in the value of these commodities is included the unpaid labour furnished by the workers and whose equivalent in value of course belongs, once again by the laws of capitalism, to Dassault and Chanel. The other capitalists buy these commodities at their value and thus realise the surplus value of their colleagues.
The labour power of the unproductive sectors has thus affirmed its productive capacity in relation to the immediate capital which purchased it, by providing that capital with a value higher than the one which it received. Labour power creates surplus value for capital. But from the viewpoint of global capital, it destroyed surplus value.
The worker exploited by an unproductive capitalist industry is just as much a proletarian as the worker in the productive sector. But whereas the surplus value created by the latter is part of the REAL surplus value which expands global capital, the surplus value produced by the workers in the unproductive sector is a source of profit only for the immediate capitalist; it is an unproductive expense for global capital.
Our point of departure was to answer the question: is arms production a solution to capitalist crises? Can it prevent a new crisis? These questions led us to pose the problem of the determination of productive labour.
The answer to this problem in turn now permits us to respond clearly to the first question; ARMS PRODUCTION IS NOT A SOLUTION TO CRISES.
The outlet constituted by military spending also represents a heavy burden for the economy of each nation.. Military spending is an incredible waste for capital and for the development of the productive forces. [12] [87]. It is estimated that in the past few decades the United States has transformed, on average, one third of its annual surplus into military goods. This means that if this spending could have been transformed into productive goods, the growth of the American economy (provided it found the necessary markets) would have been 33 per cent more rapid.
The production of a cannon implies for capital not only the loss of the labour embodied in the cannon itself but even more a sterilisation of this labour, a blockage of the continuing process of the self-expansion of capital. Capital has to bear not only the loss of past labour but also the burden of a paralysis of its productive process.
It is clear that the ‘military stimulant' can in no way assure the eternal expansion of capitalism. As an outlet it can only be an auxiliary factor (in periods of reconstruction, for example) and in any case its effects, like those of reconstruction, are of a limited duration: a nation that transformed its whole annual surplus into arms would find its economic growth totally stopped at the end of a year. A country can resume its economic expansion only by making these armaments profitable, that is through war (and then only if the country is victorious). [13] [88] The greater the share of surplus transformed into arms, the shorter the duration of the stimulating effects of this outlet, and the sooner the question of their profitability becomes pressing. The longer this solution is put off, the greater becomes the immense weight of this unproductive burden on the national economy: inflation, decline in the competitiveness of the nation's products on the world market (because the cost of these products increasingly comprises military expenses), which in its turn, through the loss of markets which results, aggravates the internal problem of a lack of outlets. The increasing pressure exerted by the American government on the European nations to take care of their own military expenses cannot be explained in any other way.
This said, we must now answer the question implicit from the beginning: if military production is so detrimental to the development of capital, why do all the countries in the world, and first and foremost the great powers, devote such an enormous part of their productive capacity to this type of production?
We have seen that the demand created by military needs possesses certain particular advantages as an outlet: for example it affects nearly all sectors of industry, while bringing special advantages to those sectors where capital is most highly concentrated.
Its role as an economic stimulant has made certain analysts conclude that the development of the armaments industry was the result of a conscious decision on the part of the capitalists to create an artificial outlet invented to fill the needs of an economy constantly threatened by suffocation due to a lack of markets. Nothing could be further from the truth. Capitalism produces commodities. Naturally its primary concern is the exchange value of the commodity, its monetary equivalent. But this does not allow it to ignore the use value of the commodity. A product which has no use value, which does not correspond to any social need whatsoever is anything but a commodity. It has no place in the capitalist world. The capitalist state which buys armaments is, like any other capitalist, a prisoner of the law of value: it can buy only what corresponds to a real need. Outlets which can be invented at will only exist in the dreams of bankrupt capitalists. The development of the armaments industry is linked to the exacerbation of the inter-imperialist antagonisms. In a world entirely split up among the competing powers and where there are too few pieces for all the competitors, the military strength of each nation becomes the indispensable, inevitable tool for its economic survival. The world wars have shown the price a country has to pay for any weakness in this domain.
It is not only armaments which are an unproductive industry for capital. Capitalist decadence since 1914 is characterised by the dizzying growth of a whole series of unproductive economic activities. All these expenses have the same raison d'etre: to moderate the growing difficulties that the economic system encounters in all areas in trying to assure its own reproduction. Armaments are only one of these activities and if we have dealt with them separately it is because of their very important role as an ‘economic stimulant'.
Among the expenditure of this type which has becoming particular important we can cite:
1. Expenditure to maintain 'social peace'. All the costs of maintaining a whole body of employees ranging from the police to the union apparatus, from welfare workers to sociology professors. Also expenses such as unemployment compensation,etc. (Great Britain, for example, has ‘maintained' more than a million unemployed for more than five years!)
2. Expenditure to moderate economic difficulties within each nation - or within each company. The incredible swelling of the general economic administration of the state: planning bodies, regulatory agencies, etc. It is necessary to add to these all the costs of subsidising failing companies and the ever growing aberrations of agriculture under capitalism: payments for letting the land lie fallow, destruction of harvests and surpluses, the cost of stabilising the agricultural markets, etc. There are also the expenditures of private companies constantly confronted with sales problems which competition makes even more acute: marketing expenses, administrative costs, and above all advertising (these costs are generally lower in state capitalist countries but any savings are offset by the enormous waste that bureaucratic irresponsibility entails in the distribution network). The development of the Tertiary sector is largely the result of this type of unproductive expenditure.
3. Expenditure caused by the aberrations resulting from the desperate actions of firms in certain countries (United States and to some extent Europe and Japan) faced with the need to compensate for the lack of markets. The most striking aspect of this phenomenon is in the reduction in the use value of consumer goods (cars, stockings, electric appliances, etc) consciously made with a view towards planned obsolescence. This technique is reinforced by advertising intended to create ‘in' fashions and therefore ‘out' fashions. Amongst these aberrations we can take the example of the automobile: at first a real social need it has gradually become a social disaster. The productive aspect of the car (a means of transportation for labour power) has more and more given way to the unproductive aspect of the commodity as a noxious waste.
4. Expenditure arising from international relations in particular, the extent of military expenditure staggers the imagination. The military expenditure of the United States and the USSR together are greater than the combined national incomes of all of Latin America plus India and Pakistan. The state of the Middle East devote around 25 per cent of their GNP to armaments. In the last ten years world capital has spent more on armaments than in the first fifty years of this century - the two world wars included.
Unproductive expenditure also existed in the ascendant phase of capitalism. Luxury goods for the ruling class, for example, have existed since the beginning of capitalism. The same is true for the police, army and the administrative costs of the state. But the extent of these expenses in the past centuries is in no way comparable to these same types of expenditures in the past sixty years.
The unproductive content of these ‘artificial' costs of production in ascendant capitalism was attenuated because the relations of production were at the time basic to the development of the productive forces. When capitalism was taking over the planet by destroying pre-capitalist relations, when it was imposing its techniques on the entire world, its relations of production were also productive forces. At the time the general costs necessary to the maintenance of the relations of production were offset by the productive nature of these relations. Therefore, when an imperialist army, for instance, imposed capitalist relations in a part of the world, world capitalism was enriched. These armies were on certain occasions true productive forces for world capitalism.
This situation completely changes the moment that the world is divided up amongst the competing powers. The war could only bring about a redivision of the spoils, any new conquest having become impossible. From that time, one capitalist power could militarily win a sphere of influence only at the expense of another power. For world capital war could only represent an internal disruption, a disastrous waste. When capitalist relations of production cease to be the instrument for the development of the productive forces and become fetters, all the ‘artificial' costs that they entail become simple waste. It is important to note that this inflation of artificial costs is an inevitable phenomenon which imposes itself on capitalism with as much violence as its contradictions.
For a half century the history of capitalist nations is filled with ‘austerity programmes', attempts to turn back the clock, struggles against the uncontrollable expansion of government costs and unproductive expenses in general. Every time international competition is aggravated in a critical fashion, the question of these expenses is more sharply raised [14] [89]. All these efforts, however, systematically end in failure. Remember the Nixon austerity plan (August 15,1972) and the anti-inflationary budget that went with it: in spite of all the speeches, military expenditures - the principle source of inflation in the United States - were once again increased. Unproductive expenditure functions for decadent capitalism like some drug, which is at once a medication and a poison, taken for certain illnesses. The worse the disease becomes, the more you have to increase the dosage; the more you increase the dosage, however, the worse the disease becomes. Inflation is the cancer of modern capitalism and unproductive expenses are its main source of nourishment. The more difficulties capitalism faces, the more it must develop its artificial costs. This vicious circle, this gangrene rotting the core of the wage labour system, is only one of the symptoms of the real disease: the decadence of capitalism. The consequences of all this have been known for more than half a century: world war or proletarian revolution: socialism or barbarism.
[1] [90] Marx, "Materiaux Pour L'Economie", in Oeuvres, Vol.2, La Pleiade, p.387
[2] [91] Marx, Capital, Vol. 1, Pt. V, Chap. XVI, in Oeuvres, Vol. 2, La Pleiade, p.1001 (We cite this French edition because it renders the passage in question more accurately than the English translation)
[3] [92] Marx, Capital, Vol. 1, Pt.3, Chap. VII, London 1970, p.180-181
[4] [93] Marx "Materiaux Pour L'Economie", in Oeuvres, Vol. 2, La Pleiade, p.392
[5] [94] Ibid, p.388
[6] [95] Ibid, p.398
[7] [96] Ibid, p.393
[8] [97] Marx, Capital, Vol 1, Pt. VII, Chap. XXIV, Section 1, London 1970, p.580-581
[9] [98] Marx, "Mareriaux Pour L'Economie", in Oeuvres, Vol. 2, La Pleiade, p.390
We can only note the ignorance both of marxism and of capitalist reality shown by ‘marxists' like H. Weber who, taking refuge in "dry and arid theory" see only "ethical criteria" in this definition of productive power.
[10] [99] The definition of productive labour under capitalism can only be related to the useful content of this labour at the point of a certain development of the system. The first capitalist manufacturers produced mainly ‘unproductive' goods: arms, gun powder, luxury cloth, etc. However, this did not pose a major problem for capitalism's development. The reason was that the capitalist sector remained a mere workshop within a process of social production still largely dominated by pre-capitalist formations (essentially feudal ones). Agricultural and artisan production could still supply the capitalist manufacturers with the basic materials for the means of production and for the consumer goods necessary for production which was functioning with an extremely low technical composition of capital, ie, in which living labour predominated dead labour. (The first workshops were often simply associations of artisans, working with the old methods, but subjected to the regime of wage-labour by an entrepreneur.)
In these conditions, the use-value content of capitalist commodities had little importance for the development of capital. It is only when the capitalist mode of production takes possession of the whole of social production ("the real domination of capital") that the definition of productive labour has to take into account its specific utility. That is why Engels could write: "At the beginning of the fourteenth century, gunpowder came from the Arabs to Western Europe, and as every school child knows, completely revolutionized the methods of warfare. The introduction of gunpowder and fire-arms, however, was not at all an act of force, but a step forward in industry, that is, an economic advance. Industry remains industry, whether it is applied to the production or destruction of things" (Engels, Anti-Duhring, Moscow 1969, p.200)
H. Weber, who had the misfortune to write on this subject in the above mentioned pamphlet, has not failed to deduce that today industry dedicated to the construction of arms, "these modern consumer goods", constitutes an industry as productive as any other. Mr. Weber really doesn't see why anyone should think that anything changes in the productive or unproductive nature of labour in Dassault's factories whether they are producing bombers or civil aviation aeroplanes. In the fifteenth century, all the capitalist enterprises could adapt themselves to producing nothing but arms and still undergo a certain expansion. That Mr. Weber portrays the same thing today and concludes that this represents capitalist expansion - all this falls within the logic of his argument.
[11] [100] We are presupposing that this nation has not external trade enabling it to deflect the unproductive impact of these industries onto other nations as in the example given above ( the example of Dassault and Peru).
[12] [101] The living labour and the means of production dedicated to this kind of production are not productive, they are not productive forces - or rather, if one wants to define them from a general abstract point of view, from the point of view of the labour process, they are sterilised, annihilated productive forces. Only the science and the techniques of the production developed in these sectors, to the extent that they remain in existence after production and only to the extent that they can be applied to the creation of productive goods, are productive forces.
[13] [102] Russia's dismantling of entire factories in Czechoslovakia and Mongolia in order to take them back to its own territory at the end of World War 2 is a spectacular illustration of the ‘profitability' of military production.
[14] [103] The success in the United States of someone like Ralph Nader, enemy of murderous cars and of products which fall apart, doesn't only derive from the anger of ‘consumers'.
The problem of the decline of capitalism is far from being exhausted and there are many questions that have still not been investigated in this study. The last half century has raised a series of new problems for revolutionary theory and furnished evidence allowing for a better understanding of the problems posed years ago. We make no pretence of having gone into all these questions, still less of having resolved them.
Our principal aims have been the following: first, to explain the basis for our conviction that the proletarian revolution has been on the agenda since World War 1. Second, to deal with the profound changes capitalist society has undergone, which make so many of the traditional positions of revolutionaries out of date: tactics which were valid in the nineteenth century have become counter-revolutionary today (parliamentarism, working in the unions, participation in national struggles). This has led us to show that only an analysis which leads to the recognition of the decadence of capitalism since 1914 allows for the integration of all the important phenomena which have appeared since then into a coherent world view:
•The curbing and slow-down of the growth of the productive forces by the dominant relations of production.
•The permanent exacerbation of antagonisms between factions of the ruling class.
•The appearance of world crises and world wars on an unprecedented scale, which get worse with each outburst.
•The inordinate development of the unproductive sectors at the expense of the productive sectors.
•The accelerated decomposition of all the ideological values of the system.
•The development of class antagonisms and the outbreak of proletarian revolutionary movements calling into question the system on a world scale.
•The development and strengthening of the state apparatus and its control over the whole of society (the general tendency to state capitalism).
All these phenomena can only be understood as expressions of the definitive inability of capitalist relations of production to fulfil the historic needs of humanity.
Those who speak of revolution today and deny the reality of decadence, fail to account for, not isolated phenomena, but the underlying dynamic which necessarily links these phenomena.
But to those who accept this interpretation of the present historical period, there remains the task of deepening the analysis of decadence and drawing out all the consequences which follow for revolutionary practice.
R. Victor.
Links
[1] https://en.internationalism.org/tag/3/15/decadence-capitalism
[2] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/intro#_ftn1
[3] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/intro#_ftnref1
[4] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch1/section1#_ftn1
[5] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch1/section1#_ftnref1
[6] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch1/section2#_ftn1
[7] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch1/section2#_ftnref1
[8] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch1/section3#_ftn1
[9] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch1/section3#_ftnref1
[10] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftn1
[11] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftn2
[12] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftn3
[13] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftn4
[14] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftn5
[15] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftn6
[16] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftnref1
[17] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftnref2
[18] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftnref3
[19] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftnref4
[20] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftnref5
[21] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch4#_ftnref6
[22] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftn1
[23] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftn2
[24] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftn3
[25] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftn4
[26] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftn5
[27] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftn6
[28] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftnref1
[29] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftnref2
[30] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftnref3
[31] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftnref4
[32] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftnref5
[33] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch5#_ftnref6
[34] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6#_ftn1
[35] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6#_ftn2
[36] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6#_ftnref1
[37] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6#_ftnref2
[38] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn1
[39] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn2
[40] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn3
[41] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn4
[42] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn5
[43] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn6
[44] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn7
[45] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn8
[46] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn9
[47] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn10
[48] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn11
[49] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn12
[50] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn13
[51] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn14
[52] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftn15
[53] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref1
[54] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref2
[55] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref3
[56] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref4
[57] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref5
[58] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref6
[59] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref7
[60] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref8
[61] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref9
[62] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref10
[63] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref11
[64] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref12
[65] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref13
[66] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref14
[67] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section1#_ftnref15
[68] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section2#_ftn1
[69] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section2#_ftn2
[70] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section2#_ftn3
[71] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section2#_ftnref1
[72] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section2#_ftnref2
[73] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch6/section2#_ftnref3
[74] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch7#_ftn1
[75] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch7#_ftnref1
[76] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn1
[77] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn2
[78] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn3
[79] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn4
[80] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn5
[81] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn6
[82] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn7
[83] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn8
[84] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn9
[85] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn10
[86] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn11
[87] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn12
[88] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn13
[89] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftn14
[90] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref1
[91] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref2
[92] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref3
[93] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref4
[94] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref5
[95] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref6
[96] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref7
[97] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref8
[98] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref9
[99] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref10
[100] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref11
[101] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref12
[102] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref13
[103] https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/decadence/ch8#_ftnref14