Published on International Communist Current (https://en.internationalism.org)

Home > Communist Organisations and Class Consciousness > 3. False theories of the party

3. False theories of the party

  • 3462 reads

The nature of the communist revolution, the characteristics of the growth of proletarian consciousness, the constitution of the proletariat into the dominant class… all these conceptions have been tackled in a very theoretical way. And we should ask what function this analysis serves. How can it help us to define the role of revolutionaries, to emphasise the differences between ideology and class consciousness? Does the nature of the communist revolution influence the intervention of communists? In fact is this not too academic a way to tackle the problem?

It is true that today revolutionaries find difficulty in theorising the concrete and complex process of the class struggle as it unfolds before their eyes. Their analyses still remain very general: too often they lack experience of and direct contact with the workers’ struggle. Fifty years of counter-revolution have lain heavily on the working class and today’s revolutionaries, after such a lengthy rupture with the revolutionary organisations of the past, are like children learning to walk. What went without saying for communists fifty years ago comes as a surprise to revol­utionaries today: what emerged from the daily practice and living intervention, the experience of the past, seems today an abstract, still vague conception. The active role of communists, their relation to the class, their effective intervention within struggles themselves… all this was put into practice and taken up in a concrete way by revolutionaries in the twenties. Revolutionaries who are today trying to revive this tradition still have much to learn. The view they have of the role of the party and its tasks still remains somewhat theoretical although it is true that the resurgence of class struggle in recent years has defined their responsibilities as a communist vanguard more concretely and more effectively than a thousand theoretical texts.

But in that case wouldn’t it have been sufficient to base the writing of this pamphlet on texts from the past? Why not start this section by scrupulously quoting the theses on the Party from the Communist International congresses? Isn’t Lenin’s What Is To Be Done? a good reference point? Unfortunately not.

In fact the theoretical texts on the party written by the Communist International in 1920-21 are not a true reflection of the practice of the Bolsheviks in 1917. They are a caricature, a deformation. They amplify on a theoretical level the confusions already present, notably in Lenin’s What is to be Done? If we have found it necessary to introduce the question of the role of revolutionaries with a global analysis of communism, of the coming to consciousness of the proletariat it is precisely because the general theoretical framework for the intervention of communists was not wholly clear for the workers’ movement of the Third International, nor even, subsequently, for the left fractions who struggled against the degeneration of the Communist International.

The reappropriation of the gains of the past does not mean copying verbatim the texts of the past, aping the revolution­ary organisations which preceded us. Reappropriating the experience of the past means also criticising it, drawing out its positive and negative lessons. The revolutionary wave of the Twenties, the reflux of struggle that followed it is an inexhaustible source of lessons. These lessons have allowed us to redefine more precisely the characteristics of the world revolution, of the process of coming to consciousness and of the self-organisation of the proletariat. It is these lessons that also allow us to better expose confusions that could, and still do, exist today on the role of the party and its relations with the working class.

The historic origins of substitutionist conceptions

  • 2642 reads

Revolutionaries at the Second Congress of the Communist International defined the role of the party in the following way:

“The Communist International rejects most decisively the view that the proletariat can carry out its revolution without having an independent political party. Every class struggle is a political struggle. The aim of this struggle, which inevitably turns into civil war, is the conquest of political power. Political power can only be seized, organised and led by a political party, and in no other way.” (‘Theses on the Role of the Party’, our emphasis.)

This position, with certain exceptions, was the position of the vast majority of revolutionaries at that time. Where did it arise? How did it develop?

The origin of this conception of the party must be sought in the general positions defended by the Second International. It coincided with a period when a flourishing capitalism could still allow the winning of lasting reforms by the working class and when revolutionaries wound up relegating the ultimate goal of revolution to a remote and inaccessible future. Social Democracy, understanding that the time was not ripe for a communist revolution, laid the emphasis on trade union work and on the need for a party to devote itself to parliamentary work. As Edward David, an English Social Democrat underlined: “…the brief flowering of revolutionism is most happily past… the party will be able to devote itself to the positive exploitation and the expansion of its parliamentary power.” This was how the ‘revisionism’ of Bernstein and Kautsky was born, i.e. the sharper and sharper separation of the economic activity of the workers (led by the unions) and their political activity (delegated to a mass parliamentary party): this could only lead to the abandonment of the final goal of the workers’ struggles. As early as 1902 Kautsky therefore was proposing a ‘gradual movement, through democratic and imperceptible means, from capitalism to communism.’ The party of the proletariat then had but one sole task - that of participating in parliament with the aim of imposing this progressive movement. The seizure of power was no longer seen as the violent overthrow by the workers themselves of the bourgeois state, as the ‘emancipation of the workers’, but as an affair of parties, as the peaceful conquest of the bourgeois state. This gross distortion of marxism brought with it another one: the proletarian party was no longer seen as that vital fraction which prepares the proletariat to take its destiny into its own hands. Instead the party became a governmental apparatus; the proletariat must delegate its political activity and its power to the party by voting for it in full confidence.

Given that the avowed goal was the ‘conquest’ of the bourgeois state the idea of mass working class political organs did not exist for Social Democracy. The only political organ of the proletariat was the party. If the state could only become proletarian under the control of the proletarian party it was logical to believe, as did the Second International, that the seizure of power could only be organised, undertaken and directed by a party. For this task, and above all in order to lead the struggle for reforms, the party must be a mass, ultra-disciplined and hierarchical organisation. The ideological heritage of bourgeois revolutions weighed heavily on these conceptions!

At the beginning of the Twentieth Century the left elements of Social Democracy began to react in a healthy way against the theses of the Second International. Their great merit lay in perceiving the new epoch that was opening up and in clarifying the role of revolutionaries in the light of that period. Their first reaction centred on the separation made by Bernstein, Kautsky and friends between economic struggles and their ultimate goal — the communist revolution. In his first writings against the Narodniks (Russian populists who supported the idea of a revolution based on the peasant commune), Lenin pointed out the final objectives of the economic struggles of the proletariat:

“The Russian Social Democrats concentrate their activity and attention on the industrial working class. When the advanced elements of this class have assimilated the ideas of scientific socialism and have understood the role of the Russian worker in history, when their ideas have become widespread and the workers have created stable organisations that can transform the present incoherent economic warfare into a conscious class struggle — then the Russian worker will rise up in the van of all the democratic elements, overthrow absolutism, and lead the Russian proletariat (side by side with the proletariat of all countries) into an open political struggle for the victory of the communist revolution.” (Lenin. Collected Works. Vol 1.)

Subsequently Lenin never ceased to struggle fiercely against the view of one part of the Social Democratic Party, the Mensheviks, who failed to see in Russia, the objective conditions for a proletarian revolution. He also turned away from the Social Democratic conception of a mass party. For Lenin the new conditions of struggle meant that there was a need for a minority vanguard party that would work for the transformation of economic struggles into political ones.

In her work Reform or Revolution (1898) Rosa Luxembourg also opposed the opportunist and counter—revolutionary deviations of the Second International. She called to mind, amongst other things that, “for Social Democracy, the struggle within the existing system, day by day, for reforms, for the amelioration of workers conditions, for democratic means, is the only way of intervening in proletarian class struggle and orientating it towards the final goal, i.e. of working for the conquest of political power and the abolition of the wage system.” (R. Luxemburg. Mass Strike, the Party and the Trade Unions, our emphasis.) Rosa Luxembourg also insisted on this unity between the economic struggle and the political struggle, on the fact that defensive struggles are merely a preparation for the final political struggle for the seizure of power.

All over the world the left of Social Democracy affirmed the need for the communist revolution that the new period had put on the agenda. This left opposition arose at Zimmerwald in 1915 and then at Kienthal in 1916 as a bulwark against the wave of chauvinism and nationalism that definitively overwhelmed the Second International and the Unions at the beginning of World War One.

But that bulwark was still weak and immature. The period had changed dramatically. The demise of Social Democracy forced revolutionaries to reject their former ‘reformist’ and unionist- conceptions. It was necessary to develop the communist programme, to adapt it to the new needs of the struggle etc. All this could not take place without casualties. And despite their bitter struggle against the ideas of the past, revolutionaries still felt the weight of Social Democracy on their shoulders. Let us not forget that the political and militant formation of such revolutionaries as Lenin, Luxembourg, Pannekoek etc were burdened by the theoretical baggage of the Second International. Most of these militants first took up arms in a period when capit­alism was still progressive and the theses of Kautsky still carried weight. To ‘cast off an old skin’ is never easy and the remnants of old ideas still cling here and there.

For example, the idea still put forward by some revolutionaries, that the proletariat could use democratic institutions to hasten the revolution. Thus at the beginning of the Twentieth Century most communists saw the Paris Commune of 1871 as a model of working class control of a democratic republic, of the use of a democratic institution as a tool for workers power.

“International Socialism considers that the republic is the only possible form of socialist emancipation - with this condition, that the proletariat tears it from the hands of the bourgeoisie and transforms it from ‘a machine for the oppression of one class by another’ into a weapon for the socialist emancipation of humanity.” (L. Trotsky,  Thirty Five Years After: 1871 — 1906.)

In fact only the Dutch Left, on the basis of Luxembourg’s analysis in Accumulation of Capital, defended the idea of the bankruptcy of bourgeois revolutions in the period of decadence and the impossibility of struggles for national liberation.

Lenin for his part saw the “need for the proletariat to use all the democratic institutions and aspirations in its class struggle against the bourgeoisie.” (Lenin, Complete Works, vol. 23, 1915—1916.) In Two Tactics of Social Democracy (1905) he defended the idea that “the proletariat must lead its democratic revolution to a successful conclusion by linking itself to the peasant masses in order to obliterate the force of autocracy.” So for the Bolsheviks the creation of any democratic nation state was progressive. For Pannekoek and the Dutch Left on the other hand only the international proletarian revolution constituted a viable perspective in an epoch when the system was revealing its historic bank­ruptcy by plunging mankind into imperialist massacres.

A further confusion still weighed on the revolutionary movement, an ideological legacy of Social Democracy: a schematic conception of the coming to consciousness of the proletariat, a distorted view of the relationship between the party and the working class. This confusion is particul­arly clear in the theses in What is to be Done? elaborated by Lenin in 1902. Lenin used this work, produced in a period of reflux in class struggle, in his battle against a school of ideas prevalent in Russia at that time: Economism. A minor offspring of the theories of Bernstein, this current extolled the need for the class struggle to remain on a strictly economic terrain. In contrast to this conception which transformed Marxism into an ideology of historic fatalism, which made a cult out of the passive spontaneity of the workers and condemned the party to inactivity, Lenin showed very forcefully the need for the proletariat to go beyond the economic to the political struggle and defended the power of revolutionary theory and activity. Starting from a correct concern to put forward the ultimate goal of the economic struggle Lenin ended up ‘bending the stick’ too far the other way. Although his aim was to respond to this false separation, introduced by the Economists, between the economic and political aspects of the struggle, by emphasising the political character of these struggles Lenin was led to underestimate the economic struggle. Defensive struggles were no longer seen as a fertile soil for the development of class-consciousness: the political dimension of the movement developed ‘outside the sphere of the relations of production’. The economic and political would meet of course, but somewhat in the manner of two parallel lines that meet at infinity. Furthermore the party becomes the sole body capable of organising this fusion and of bringing consciousness to the workers.

It is therefore not surprising that Lenin took up in his book whole passages from Kautsky’s writings, for his argument rested in fact upon a Social Democratic line of argument. The keystone to What is to be Done? is contained in this now famous quotation taken from an article by Kautsky in Neue Zeit in 1901.

“Of course Socialism, as a doctrine, has its roots in modern economic relationships just as the class struggle of the proletariat has and, just as the latter, emerges from the struggle against the capitalist created poverty and misery of the masses. But socialism and the class struggle arise side by side and not one out of the other; each arises under different conditions. Modern socialist consciousness can arise only on the basis of profound scientific knowledge. Indeed modern economic science is as much a condition for socialist production as, say, modern tech­nology and the proletariat can create neither the one nor the other, no matter how much it my desire to do so; both arise out of the modern social process. The vehicle of science is not the proletariat but the bourgeois intelligentsia: it was in the minds of individual members of this stratum that modern socialism originated and it was they who communicated it to the more intellectually developed proletarians who, in their turn, introduce it into the proletarian class struggle where conditions allow that to be done. Thus socialist consciousness is something introduced into the proletarian class struggle from without and not something that arose within it spontaneously.”

The idea that class consciousness does not arise in a mechanical way from economic struggles is quite correct. But Lenin’s error was to believe that class consciousness cannot develop on the basis of economic struggles and must be introduced from the outside by a party. This incorrect view of the relationship between the party and the workers’ struggles leads to a form of mysticism that finally caused these words to fall from Lenin’s pen.

“…but what is the role of Social Democracy if it is not to be ‘the spirit’ which not only soars above the spontaneous movement but raises it to its programme?” (Lenin, What is to be Done?)

What is more, this apology for technical and scientific knowledge being the unique property of the intellectual specialists fused very neatly with Social Democracy’s vision of the seizure of power by the proletariat. Since the bourgeois state had to be seized by a party and used for the benefit of the proletariat the seizure of power demanded the existence of qualified and intelligent technicians capable of taking over the reins of administrative power!

In her work Social Reform or Revolution Rosa Luxemburg had already put her finger on other aberrations produced by this separation between class consciousness and the struggle itself, between the economic and political aspects of the proletarian struggle. In placing socialist consciousness outside the relations of production Kautsky and Lenin reduced the communist revolution and its development to an abstract and religious ideal. From such a standpoint the socialist programme and, the need for revolution are no longer the fruit of economic realities, the product of the objective conditions of the class struggle. They no longer reflect the ever more blatant internal contradictions of capitalism or the imminence of its collapse but reduce it to an ‘ideal’ whose force of persuasion rests only on the perfection attributed to it. Luxemburg continues her critique:

“We have here, in brief, the explanation of the socialist programme by means of ‘pure reason’. We have here, to use simpler language, an idealist explanation of socialism. The objective necessity of socialism, the explanation of socialism as the result of the material development of society, falls to the ground.” (Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution, 1898.)

In 1904 in a more direct response to What Is To Be Done? she outlines the global framework in which the intervention of revolutionaries is situated.

“The international movement of the proletariat towards its complete emancipation is a process peculiar in the following respect. For the first time in the history of civilisation the people are expressing their will consciously and in opposition to all ruling classes. But this will only be satisfied beyond the bounds of the existing system. Now the mass can only acquire and strengthen this will in the course of their day to day struggle against the existing social order — that is, within the limits of capitalist society. On the one hand we have the mass; on the other its historic goal located outside of existing society. On the one hand we have the day-to-day struggle, on the other the social revolution. Such are the terms of the dialectical contradiction through which the socialist movement makes its way. It follows that this movement can best advance by tacking betwixt and between the two dangers by which it is constantly being threatened. One is the loss of its mass character, the other the abandonment of its goal. One is the danger of sinking back to the condition of a sect; the other the danger of becoming a movement of bourgeois social reform.” (Luxemburg, ‘Organisational Question of Social Democracy’, in Die Neue Zeit, 1904, our emphasis.)

In a polemic that also opposed Lenin, Trotsky took up this correct and dialectical view of the relation between the daily struggle of the proletariat and class consciousness. In a passage entitled ‘Down with Political Substitutionism’ he wrote in 1904:

“The system of political substitutionism, just like the simplistic system of the ‘economists’ proceeds — consciously or not — from an inability to understand the relationship between the objective interests of the proletariat and its consciousness. Marxism teaches that the interests of the proletariat are determined by the objective conditions of its existence. These interests are so powerful and so ineluctable that they finally compel the proletariat to make the realisation of its objective interests its subjective interest. Between these two factors — the objective fact of its class interests and its subjective consciousness — lies the domain that is part of all life - the domain of conflicts and confrontations, errors and disappointments, vicissitudes and defeats. The tactical perspicacity of the proletarian party lies entirely in between these factors and consists in shortening and facilitating the road from one to the other.” (Trotsky, Our Political Tasks, 1904, our emphasis.)

This living and dialectical view of the revolution — in which the proletariat takes its own destiny into its own hands — is Trotsky’s answer to the rigid conception which limits the revolutionary process to a purely technical and organisational preparation of the proletariat for its dictatorship.

But it would be a caricature to simply contrast the substitutionist What Is to be Done of Lenin with the wholly clear and healthy vision of Rosa and Trotsky. The latter, let us not forget, came in the Twenties to defend the militarisation of Labour and the all-powerful dictatorship of the party.

In the first place, Lenin himself, to some extent, ‘corrected’ the gist of What Is to be Done. In his later works, which were enriched by the concrete experience of the class and the appearance of councils in 1905, as well as in his militant activity, he was a long way from mechanically following the theses of What Is to be Done. On the contrary the Bolshevik Party throughout its intervention in the defensive struggles of the class asserted itself not as an outside element but as an active and vital fraction of the proletariat. The entire revolutionary movement was far from being totally clear on the question of the relation between the party and the class.

Rosa Luxemburg and the German revolutionaries were no more capable than the Russian revolutionaries of severing completely the umbilical cord that tied them to Social Democracy. It is true that Luxemburg was the first to break from the doctrines of Trotsky. When, after 1910 she accused him of opening the floodgates to opportunism she was not supported by any Russian Social Democrat, and most notably not by Lenin, who found her accusations ‘exaggerated’. However it was Lenin and not Rosa who urged most clearly and most rapidly for an organisational split from the most opportunist elements of the Russian Social Democratic Party: the Mensheviks. Luxemburg and Kautsky were, in contrast, in agreement f or once since both criticised this ‘splitting’ policy and called for the reunification of Russian Social Democracy.

Up until events forced the creation of the German Communist Party in 1919 (KPD) Luxemburg remained hesitant. She hesitated to leave the Social Democratic Party (SPD); she hesitated to form a separate organisation which, at first, ran the risk of being a minority organisation; she retreated before Lenin’s persistent desire to create a new Communist International…

Luxemburg was not attached to the SDP in Germany because of any lack of political perception about the objective decay of Social Democracy. In the Crisis of Social Democracy, published in 1916 she fiercely criticised the attitude of the Second International to the imperialist war and the support given by Social Democracy to the national bourgeoisie. No, what imprisoned Luxemburg and made her hesitate was her general conception of mass revolutionary action and the consequences of this for the role of the party.

This militant, who had passed through the school of Social Democracy, developed such an unconditional attachment to the mass character of the revolutionary movement that, for her, the party had to adapt itself to anything that bore this character. Because of her attachment to the Social Democratic vision of the mass party Luxemburg was reluctant to go in advance of the movement. She hesitated to leave an organisation in which the majority of workers still had confidence. Even after the overt and definitive demise of the SPD and the 2nd International in 1914 Luxemburg continued to reiterate that it was for the mass movement to overcome opportunism; revolutionaries could not accelerate this movement.

For her the “errors committed by a truly revolutionary workers’ movement are historically more fruitful and more precious than the infallibility of the finest central committee” (Organisational Questions of Social Democracy) Thus revolutionaries could not take the initiative in going beyond the old Social Democratic organisations.

Luxemburg’s general concern was correct — the insistence on the collective character of the workers’ movement — but the insistence that “the emancipation of the workers is the task of the workers themselves” brought with it incorrect practical conclusions. And a simple concern can easily fall into idealisation, into fetishism. Fetishism of everything that has a mass character leads revolutionaries down the dangerous road of the opportunism of the Second International. An attachment to the mass character of this or that organisation or political tool can lead simply to supporting parliamentary politics (‘because the mass of workers continue to vote’). Paul Levi, a prominent representative of the KPD after Luxemburg’s death followed that path. His conception of a ‘mass party’, which would be entirely subordinate to the movement of the masses, led him to fall gradually back into the clutches of Social Democracy. This was why he urged the fusion of the KPD with the left of the SPD, rejoined the USPD in 1922 having been excluded from the CI and finally rejoined the SPD.

Luxemburg never came to understand the fact that the collective character of revolutionary activity is something that grows and develops. The homogenisation of proletarian consciousness is not made once and for all. The party effectively remains a minority when the vast majority of the working class are subjugated by bourgeois ideology. Its task consists then, not in bending itself to the dominant ideology of the masses, but in defending on a political level, as well as on an organisational level, the entire communist programme. Only in this way can the party effectively play a role in the homogenisation of class consciousness.

The German revolutionaries, like most revolutionaries of that time, were not entirely clear about the process by which the proletariat seizes power. On the whole communists saw in the workers councils the organs for the seizure of power. And in every case up to 1920 the CI insisted on the predominant role of the councils in the revolution and in the exercise of power. However, no communist, no revolutionary organisation saw very clearly the relations that should exist between the territorial soviets (the basis of the transitional state) and the workers councils. Confusion existed between the state and the dictatorship of the proletariat.

Furthermore the speech made by Luxemburg at the founding congress of the KPD (Spartacist League) in 1918 left room for very grave ambiguities. The text lacks political clarity, particularly on the destruction of the bourgeois state by the proletariat:

“So the conquest of power for us will not be effected at one blow. It will be a progressive act for we shall progressively occupy all the positions of the capitalist state, defending tooth and nail each one that we seize… the councils must have all power in the state... step by step, by hand to hand fighting, in every province, in every town, in every village, in every commune, all the powers of the state have to be transferred bit by bit from the bourgeoisie to the workers’ and soldiers’ councils.”

What does this text suggest?

1. that the proletariat must involves themselves in the bourgeois state in order to destroy it (a position which allowed the vestiges of revolutionary parliamentarianism to appear.)

2. that the proletariat should use the bourgeois state to its own advantage.

3. that the workers’ dictatorship is expressed through a proletarian state.

So it is understandable that this conception of the revolution that resembles the schema of bourgeois revolutions led revolutionaries to envisage the need for the proletarian party to take power. The Spartacists did not defend a position very different from that of Lenin but they laid strong emphasis on the ‘mass’ character of the party’s seizure of power.

“The Spartacist League refuses to take over the power of government merely because the Scheidemann—Ebert element have completely discredited themselves... The Spartacist League will never take over the power of government otherwise than by a clear manifestation of the unquestionable will of the great majority of the proletarian mass of Germany.” (Proposed programme adopted by the KPD (Spartacists) at its foundation in 1918. Published in Die Rote Fahne Dec. 1918.)

To the question ‘What are the origins of substitutionism?’ we can respond: the weight of Social Democratic conceptions. But to the question ‘What are the causes which allowed the development of substitutionist conceptions?’ we must reply: the general political immaturity of the international working class.

“The first imperialist world war signalling the end of the period of capitalist ascendancy marked the absolute point of no return for the workers’ movement of the 19th Century and its immediate objectives. Popular discontent against the war became rapidly politicised into frontal attacks against the state in key countries of Europe. But the majority of the proletariat was unable to cast off the relics of the past, (adherence to the policies of the Second International which was now in the camp of the class enemy) and to fully under­stand the implications of the new era. Neither the proletariat as a whole nor its political organisations fully understood the needs of the proletarian struggle in the new age of ‘war and revolution’, ‘socialism or barbarism’. Despite the heroic struggles of the proletariat in this period the tide of revolution was drowned in the massacre of the working class in Europe. The fact that the Russian revolution was the beacon for all the working class in that epoch did not alter the fact that its isolation was a serious danger. Even a temporary gap between revolutionary outbreaks can have its dangers but by 1920 the gap was becoming increasingly unbridgeable.” (Judith Allen. ‘The Degeneration of the Russian Revolution’, in International Review No. 3, 1975.)

However as long as the class was sufficiently strong and the revolutionary movement was on the upturn the theoretical confusions about the relations between the class, the party and the state could be overcome by the concrete experience of struggle. Thus the practice of the workers in Russia confirmed the material impossibility for a workers’ party, even if it is a minority of the class, to substitute itself for the activity of the entire working class.

The question of who took power in Russia in October 1917 is answered by history and the practice of the proletariat itself. On the eve of the insurrection the Petrograd Soviet felt itself sufficiently strong and sufficiently supported by the provinces to call for the convocation of a Congress of Soviets and urge it to prepare for the armed insurrection. The Soviet believed that the Congress had a role in “giving a solution to the problems of the organisation of revolutionary power.” After untiring propaganda by the Bolshevik Party within the Soviets and the factory committees, the majority of workers finally declared themselves in favour of the seizure of power. From a military viewpoint it was the Revolutionary Committee that in Petrograd prepared the insurrection. This committee, which was composed of representatives from the Soviets, from the navy, the factory committees, the railways and the Red Guard (armed workers) was not an organ of the party, even if the Bolsheviks were dominant inside it. The Revolutionary Committee stayed in permanent contact with the whole of the working class and never ceased to act under its control; it was an organ that was directly linked to the Soviets and the factory committees. Not for an instant did the contact between the barracks, the factories, the committee and the party break down. A vital and continuous link existed between all the organs cementing the collective will of the class. The workers as a whole made decisions and held in their hands the reins of history, even if the day-to-day military actions were implemented by a small number of people. This is why, when he was accused of taking power with a small group of ‘conspirators’ i.e. the Revolutionary Committee, Trotsky replied:

“Professor Pokrovsky denies the very importance of the alternative: soviet or party. Soldiers are no formalists, he laughs: they did not need a Congress of Soviets in order to overthrow Kerensky. With all its wit such a formulation leaves unexplained the problem: why create soviets at all if the party is enough? ‘It is interesting’ continues the professor,’ that nothing at all came of this aspiration to do everything almost legally, with soviet legality, and the power at the last moment was taken not by the soviet but by an obviously illegal organisation, created ad hoc,’ Pokrovsky here cites the fact that Trotsky was compelled ‘in the name of the Military Revolutionary Committee’ and not the Soviet to declare the government of Kerensky non—existent. A most unexpected conclusion. The Military Revolutionary Committee was an elected organ of the Soviet. The leading role of the committee in the overturn did not in any sense violate that soviet legality which the professor makes fun of but which the masses were extremely jealous of.” (Trotsky. History of the Russian Revolution, vol. 3, our emphasis.)

What do these phrases mean? Do they suggest that the October Revolution took place within strict bourgeois legality, under the protection of formal democracy, with no clandestine activity? Of course not! The ‘Soviet Legality’ of which Trotsky spoke was very simply the need for the collective will of the workers, for their control over the whole of the revolutionary process. The seizure of power in Russia showed in an astounding way how the workers as a whole can decide and control the revolution. In his History of the Russian Revolution Trotsky describes how this control was concretised and how the workers prepared the insurrection through the Soviets.

No party substituted itself for the practical and decisive activity of the workers. The Bolsheviks acted in a decisive way within their class but they did not take power in the place of the workers. However theoretical confusions existed on the nature of the relations between the party, the working class and the state, and on the role of the party. And since the party is not simply a passive reflection of consciousness these misunderstandings, which had existed in embryo since 1902, would expand and accelerate the degeneration of the revolution. From 1918 on the political power of the working class was being restricted and stifled by the state apparatus at whose head stood the Bolshevik party. Since the seizure of power the Bolshevik Party had entered into conflict with the unitary organs of the proletariat and presented itself as a party of government. This substitution of the councils’ power by that of the party was justified theoretically (along with the militarisation of labour) in Trotsky’s work Terrorism and Communism written at the beginning of the Twenties — a tragic work which already contained the theor­etical justification for acts like the Kronstadt massacre.

“We have more than once been accused of having substituted for the dictatorship of the soviets the dictatorship of our party. Yet it can be said with complete justice that the dictatorship of the soviets became possible only by means of the dictatorship of the party. It is thanks to the clarity of its theoretical vision and its strong revolutionary organisation that the party has afforded to the soviets the possibility of becoming transformed from shapeless parliaments of labour into the apparatus of the supremacy of labour. In this ‘substitution’ of the power of the party for the power of the working class there is nothing accidental, and in reality there is no substitution at all. The communists express the fundamental interests of the working class. It is quite natural that in the period in which history brings up those interests in all their magnitude on to the order of the day that the communists have become the recognised representation of the working class as a whole.” (Trotsky. Terrorism or Communism.)

Once the party and the state become the avowed ‘representatives’ of the working class as a whole they could never be wrong, they were always right even in opposition to the entire working class, even at the price of massacres. From that instant socialism itself becomes the affair of the party and of the state. From that moment the Russian state began destroying the councils that meant destroying the strength of the revolution and sinking deep into counterrevolution.

And alongside these serious confusions the Communist Inter­national was developing the concept of the United Front, the idea of defending a minimum programme with a mass party, the need for union work, the positions of revolutionary parliamentarianism etc. Rather than trying to go against the reflux in the revolutionary wave and to hold communist principles intact the CI was bending itself more and more to this retreat and was also adapting its practices. Differences between ‘tactics’ and principles developed, as they had within the Second International. Rather than always keeping in mind the international interests of the proletariat the CI became more and more the mouthpiece of the Russian State and sounded its death knell when it adopted the theory of Socialism in One Country. These theses defended by the CI were merely brought forward to defend the strengthening of state capitalism in Russia. From that point on the Bolshevik Party became the most docile tool of the counterrevolution.

The heritage of the CI and the reactions to its degeneration

  • 1865 reads

A human body attacked by germs will always give rise to a reaction. It secretes anti—bodies to try to check the evil and destroy it. A revolutionary proletarian organisation reacts in the same way. Even if seriously attacked by the virus of bourgeois ideology the revolutionary organisation can still be saved from death. As long as a spark of life remains intact it impels a healthy reaction within itself, a sort of defence mechanism. But the moment that the ailing organisation leaves the proletarian camp its death is irreversible. There is nothing left for the proletariat to do but to definitively abandon the corpse and undertake the reconstruction of a new weapon of struggle.

The progressive degeneration of the Communist International provoked an upsurge amongst the healthiest revolutionary elements. But how difficult this upsurge was! Those who today pretend to invent everything anew and who judge history from their superior intellectual heights in fact adopt a purely infantile attitude, imagining what ‘should have been’ in that period and condemning every thing that goes outwith their abstract schemas. We don’t judge history, but draw from it lessons for the future. It would also be ludicrous for us to analyse the reflux of the revolutionary wave and the death agony of the Communist International as if they were the products of the machiavellian plans of the Bolsheviks! — as if they had been preparing their coup since 1902. It would also be ridiculous to idealise any left fraction that emerged in the Communist International, endowing it with all the virtues of truth. The process of counterrevolution that condemned the CI sowed terrible confusion within the workers’ movement. Even those who pursued the task of theoretical elaboration during the dark years of the 30s, the elements of the Communist Left, had to look for a long time in order to see all the implications of the defeat. No left fraction held all the keys to the problems, or the ‘whole truth’. All retained traces of the terrible defeat and their political positions were all deformed in one way or another. For the ordeal through which these revolutionaries had passed was indeed a terrible one.

Their class was crushed on an international level after 1927; the bastion of the world revolution became progressively more isolated and was transformed into a bastion of the counterrevolution; their international organisation was definitively dead from the moment it adopted the theory of ‘Socialism in One Country’; their British, German, Dutch and Danish comrades, who became progressively more isolated, were forced by the CI to fuse with centrists and opportunists of the most vile sort, under pain of expulsion... under these crushing blows many simply hung their heads and submitted. Nevertheless some had enough militant courage and revolution­ary will to continue struggling.

Those who reacted to the degeneration of the Communist International were few and they never managed to form an organised and cohesive international opposition. Their appearance in some parts of the world (from Mexico to Asia, and of course including Russia) was not really coordinated at a political or organisational level. Although many contacts and exchanges were made, notably between the KAPD, Bordiga’s fraction, the British comrades round Pankhurst, the Belgian left etc., although Il Soviet (organ of the Italian Left) published many texts from the left current and although international contacts existed up until the Second World War, the weight and force of the impact of the counterrevolution hurled the left fractions into profound isolation.

We don’t have time to look at all the left fractions or oppositions which appeared within the International; we will have to be content simply with analysing how the most significant left currents reacted to the specific positions of the Bolsheviks and the CI on the party.

The Italian Left

Without going into all the political and historical details which led to the formation of the Italian Left we’ll simply say that as far back as 1926 - the date of its expulsion from the Italian Communist Party — the Italian Left, led by Bordiga, was to fight mainly against

1. The CI’s conception of ‘revolutionary parliamentarianism’.

2. The idea of the united front and the directives of the CI concerning the formation of communist parties by joining with centrist and clearly bourgeois elements.

3. The Russian state’s development towards a bourgeois state and the Communist International’s gradual abandonment of internationalist positions.

4. The communist parties’ gradual development towards becoming bourgeois nationalist parties through their participation in the Second World War in the name of ‘anti—fascism’ and the ‘defence of democracy’.

However on the question of the role of the party and its relation to the working class the Italian Left proved unable to draw all the lessons of the degeneration of the Russian Revolution. In fact the Italian Left was to return to the positions and theses of the CI, in their entirety, on the role of the party in the revolution (adopted in 1920). This is demonstrated by the texts of the Italian Left Communists that were published of 1921/2. In these texts Bordiga embraces once more the old separation, developed by Lenin in What is to be Done, between economic and political struggles. By starting out from a subtle reasoning which condemns static photographs of reality that see social classes as economic entities without movement, Bordiga arrives at the incorrect conclusion that the working class can define itself as a thinking, acting class only through a revolutionary minority. The proletariat does not define itself economically but solely through its political movement, the party. Thus by beginning from the correct premise that the class is not simply an economic category and that the revolutionary party is indispensable to the homogenisation of its political consciousness, Bordiga reaches an absurd conclusion. He ends up, quite simply, without wanting to, by erasing those economic and material determinations that form the real basis of class consciousness and of the very existence of the party. In exactly the same way as Kautsky when he made a separation between reforms and revolution, Bordiga too ends up by placing the needs of the communist revolution not within material contingencies, but in the perfection of an ideal.

By developing the idea that you cannot talk about class consciousness and even class action outside the activity of the party, by in a sense making the existence of the party precede that of the working class, the Italian Left walks on its hands with its feet in the air. If the consciousness of the class and its will to act can only be condensed and concretised in the class party, and if it is not the proletarian struggle which itself expresses and produces this movement towards consciousness by secreting revolutionary organisations, if this is how it is, then where does the party come from? How does it arise? Does it come from the heavens? The only answer that seems to satisfy our Bordigists of yesterday and today is that in What is to be Done, i.e. revolutionaries are intellectuals who possess the ‘know-how’ and the understanding, and who bring consciousness complete to the workers. They are elements external to the proletariat.

It is this simplistic and false conception that appears in the texts of the PCI (Programma Communista), which today represents the worst caricature of the Italian Left. On the one hand, say the PCI, we have the masses who are incapable of going beyond immediatism without the directing intervention of the party, the Commander—in—chief of the proletarian troops. On the other hand we have the party, the only body capable of really acting on and thinking about the historic interests of the proletariat, the sole bearer of the invariant communist programme. In as far as the revolution is, despite everything, a conscious revolution, (the PCI is forced to admit this) it is essential that this revolution is led, directed and set up by the only conscious organ of the proletariat, its party. So it is logical that it should take power, and take on the dictatorship of the proletariat, as it is the party that ensures the constitution of the proletariat into a class struggling for its own emancipation. The dictatorship of the proletariat will thus be the dictat­orship of the communist party and it will be a party of government. (cf. the ‘Theses of the Abstentionist Fraction of the Italian CP’, 1920.)

But the question which must be posed in the face of such sledge—hammer arguments is this: if the workers are only a herd of mindless sheep why should they follow the commands of revolutionaries rather than those of the bourgeoisie? How will they be capable of distinguishing the revolutionary direction the party is proposing? Let’s hear the response of the PCI. “If the proletariat follows the party it’s not under the influence of passive obedience. It is clearly absurd to conclude that the party ordains and the class ‘obeys” But neither, according to the PCI, is it because the masses possess an ounce of the party’s divine intelligence; it is because:

“If the party can and must become an effective organ of leadership, if it can and must win the decisive influence that will enable it to constrain the soviets and lead them to power, it is because it possesses over the rest of the mass of proletarians the advantage of knowing the general results and conditions of the proletarian movement, as it says in the Manifesto; it is because at each moment of the class struggle, and also in advance of future developments, it can and must indicate the objectives, the methods and the organisation that will make this struggle as effective as possible and make it advance towards its final goals; it is because it can and must give practical political answers to the problems posed to the workers by the needs of the struggle.” (Le Proletaire, No. 269. ‘No revolutionary action without party leadership.’ June 1978,)

Observe the shining clarity of this response! If the workers follow the orders of the party it is because “they can and must follow them”. If the workers are capable of following them it is because the “party can and must be the clearest”! What could be more natural, in fact. Once upon a time the good words of the priest were followed blindly or ‘of their own free will’ by the faithful, because the priest claimed to be the incarnation of divine will. Tomorrow the workers will follow the words of the party because it claims to embody the path to communism. So it is the miraculous virtue of pol­itical clarity per se which will lead the workers to obey the directives of the party.

What a rigid, sterile and impoverished vision. What the Bordigists, stuck behind their spectacles, can never see is the living class struggle. For if it is not indissolubly linked to the workers’ struggles, to the ever greater cap­acity of the proletariat (stimulated by the objective con­ditions as well as by the intervention of revolutionaries) to understand and put into practice a political framework of its own, forged in its own experience - then the party’s theoretical clarity can only wither away, becomes sclerotic and even die.

The question of understanding why the workers will take the direction put forward by their party is not simply founded on programmatic correctness. If the workers are content to apply the ‘directives’ of the party — however correct they are —without understanding and without assimilating them into daily experience, without seeing in them an expression of their global historic interests, they are only representing an attitude which leaves them bound hand and foot on the terrain of the bourgeoisie. The communist revolution would be ser­iously compromised by this, for such weak political conviction on the part of the workers could be used profitably by the class enemy.

The only guarantee for the revolution does not rest on the workers’ obedience, even active obedience, to the directives of the party, but on their collective strength, on their global capacity to understand the goals and the means of revolutionary activity, on their collective class consciousness.

All the confusions on the party that exist in the groups which have come out of the Italian communist left are based precisely on this fundamental lack of understanding of the nature of the communist revolution and of how the proletariat comes to consciousness. The Bordigists reduce a whole living, complex and collective process to a question of technical and military preparation. The communist revolution, which they identify as the seizure of state power by the party, requires ‘specialist’ professional revolutionaries capable of taking over the reins of government. Readopting the old confusions of the Bolsheviks about the relation between the party, the state and the class, they make a simple identification between the bourgeoisie’s seizure of power and the communist insurrection.

“After having conquered control of the state the proletariat must undertake complex functions… It would be a fund­amental mistake to believe that such a degree of preparation and specialisation could be achieved merely by organising the workers on a trade basis according to their traditional funct­ions in the old regime… We will instead have to con­front tasks of a much more complex nature which require a synthesis of political, administrative, and military preparation. Such a preparation, which must exactly correspond to the pre­cise historical tasks of the proletarian revolution, can be guaranteed only by the political party; in effect the political party is the only organism which possesses on one hand a general historical vision of the revolutionary process and of its necessities and on the other hand a strict organisation of all its particular functions to the final general aim of the class… It is for this reason that the rule of the class can only be the rule of the party.” (Bordiga. ‘Party and Class Action’, 1921.)

In response to this view which delegates the accomplishment of the revolution to a minority of political ‘spec­ialists’ (as happened in revolutions in the past), we simply offer two quotations. The first is taken from Trotsky’s work ‘Our Political Tasks’ written in the heat of the polemic against What is to be Done,

“At, the very moment that Lenin was creating his formula of the social democratic Jacobin, his political friends in the Urals were elaborating a new formula for the dictatorship of the proletariat. ‘If the Paris Commune of 1871 failed — say the Uralian marxists — it’s because diverse tendencies were represented within it, often contradictory and opposed to each other. Everyone put his oar in, and this led to much dispute and little action…. It must be said that the proletariat, not only in Russia but worldwide, must be pre­pared and prepare itself to receive a strong and powerful organisation… The preparation of the proletariat for the dictatorship is such an important organisational task that all others must be subordinated to it. This preparation consists, among other things, of creating a state of mind in favour of a strong and powerful organisation, of explaining its meaning. One might object that dictators have appeared and have done so on their own. But it hasn’t always been like this, and the proletarian party must reject all spontaneism and opportunism. It must unite itself at a higher degree of knowledge and with an absolute will… the one must imply the other…’

This philosophy can be summed up in three theses:

1. The preparation of the proletariat for the dictatorship is a problem of organisation. It consists in preparing the proletariat to ‘receive’ a powerful organisation, crowned by a ‘dictator’.

2. In the interests of the dictatorship of the proletariat, it’s indispensable to consciously prepare for the appear­ance of this dictatorship over the proletariat.

3. Any deviation from this programme is a manifestation of opportunism.

In any case, the authors of this document have the courage to say loudly that, to them, the dictatorship of the proletariat looks like a dictatorship over the proletariat: it is not the working class which, through its autonomous action, has taken the destiny of society into its own hands, but a ‘strong and powerful organisation’ which, reigning over the proletariat and through this over society as a whole, will ensure the passage to socialism.

In fact, to prepare the working class for political rule, it’s indispensable to develop and cultivate its self—activity, the habit of activity, permanently controlling all the executive personnel of the revolution. This is the great political task of international social democracy. But for the ‘social dem­ocratic Jacobins’, for the intrepid representatives of political substitutionism, the enormous social and political task of preparing a class for state power is replaced by an organisational—tactical task: the fabrication of an apparatus of power.

The first approach stresses methods of educating and re-educating ever-growing layers of the proletariat, by making them participate in active political work. The second reduces everything to the selection of disciplined executives of the different echelons of the ‘strong and powerful organisation’ - a selection, which, to make the work easier, can only be ach­ieved by the mechanical elimination of those who are unsuitable.” (Trotsky. Our Political Tasks, 1904.)

Subsequently, Trotsky correctly compared this position of the ‘Uralian’ tendency with that of the Blanquists. In fact, Blanquism was also characterised by a lack of understanding of the immense differences which separate the proletarian revolution, made by the ‘vast majority’ of the exploited over the ‘minority of exploiters’, from earlier bourgeois revolutions, made by the “exploiting minority against the exploited majority”. The angle from which the Bordigists today view the role of the party in the revolution is a Blanquist one. So they see the party as a steel bloc made up of clairvoyant specialists which emerges “when the time has come to build the complete mono­lithic and exclusive edifice of its own theory”. (Programme Communiste No. 76). Posing as the sole defenders of workers’ consciousness, our Bordigist comrades not only have a megalomaniac and infantile spirit, but also a conspiratorial and putschist view of the revolution. Their caricature of’ a party goes hand in hand with a caricature of the communist revolution.

This warped view of the proletarian revolution has already been adequately criticised by marxists in the 19th century. This is what Engels said of the Blanquists’ idea of their role at the moment of the socialist revolution.

“Brought up in the school of conspiracy, and held together by the strict discipline which went with it, they started out from the viewpoint that a relatively small number of resolute, well—organised men would be able, at a given favourable moment, not only to seize the helm of state, but also by a display of great, ruthless energy, to maintain power until they succeeded in sweeping the mass of the people into revolution and ranging them round the small band of leaders. This involved, above all, the strictest, dictatorial centralisation of all power in the hands of the new revolutionary government..” (Engels, Introduction to the Civil War in France.)

These two quotations suffice to show the logical and necessary link between the idea one has of the role of revolutionaries in the communist revolution, and the nature of the revolution itself. Overestimating the role of the party means cutting off the revolution from its vital collective strength. Likewise, to give the party the power to embody class consciousness is to prevent the full flowering of that consciousness; it means taking the immediate state of consciousness of the great mass of workers as a fait accompli, making rigid its weaknesses. It does no great service to the proletariat to entrust its rev­olutionary minority with all the tasks that demand consciousness and determination. On the contrary, this attitude can only encourage submission to the dominant ideology. By acting in this way, revolutionaries turn themselves into an obstacle on the path to revolution.

It is in order to avoid this trap that we insist so strongly on the gulf which separates communism from the social trans­formations which have preceded it. And it is for this reason also that we have tried to differentiate class consciousness from simple ideology.

In fact the substitutionist conceptions about the role of the party are not only founded on a lack of understanding of the specificity of the proletarian dictatorship, nor on a confusion between the transitional state, the party and the working class. These conceptions emerge logically from a restricted theory, from an erroneous analysis of class consciousness. Most of the groups that came out of the Italian left took up the same theoretical errors as Lenin and Kautsky. They do not see the true identity that exists between economic and political struggles, between proletarian theory and practice. They do not see class consciousness as a living process, as the affirm­ation of the conscious being of the proletariat. The idea of the party being outside the class arises from the identification of class consciousness with an ideology. So it is normal that, for the Bordigists, consciousness should be a feat of intellec­tual understanding, marxism a ‘science’, and the communist programme a fixed doctrine. It is also normal in that case that revolutionaries should be seen as ever—so—wise profess­ionals in politics, whose job is to bear consciousness to the workers.

These confusions are also to be found amongst the less sclerotic and less monolithic groups of the Italian left. In a text in Prometeo, the theoretical organ of the Partito Comunista Internazionaliste (Battaglia Comunista), the following analysis of class consciousness appears:

“Once again we have to return to the essential point of com­munist doctrine… according to which there exists a great difference between ‘class instinct’ and ‘class consciousness’. The first is born and develops within workers’ struggles as the patrimony of the workers themselves; it comes from the antagonism of material interests and is nourished by the growing economic, social, and political contradictions brought about by this antagonism; finally, it depends on a certain degree of tension in the relationship between proletarians and capitalists. The second, consciousness, is born out of the scientific examination of class contradictions, it grows with the growth of knowledge of these contradictions it lives and is nourished by the examination and elaboration of facts coming from the historic experiences of the class…

Consciousness is therefore precisely an element ‘introduced into the proletarian class struggle from without where con­ditions allow that to be done’ (Kautsky, cited by the ICC in a polemical fashion in Revolution Internationale No. 12). The arguments of the ICC don’t demonstrate what they aim to demon­strate, on the contrary, they show that these comrades know nothing of dialectics…

In other words, nothing that the ICC says alters the fact (or could do so) that ‘The vehicle of science is not the pro­letariat’ (again Kautsky and Lenin cited by the ICC); neither have they understood the Marx of The German Ideology…

Are the ruling ideas the ideas of the ruling class, or not? Is it or is it not true that those who possess the material means of production also possess the intellectual means of production and that the proletariat on the other hand is an exploited, and thus, an ideologically dominated, class?

If this is true, then it’s also true that ‘it was in the minds of individual, members of this stratum that modern Socialism originated: it was they who communicated it to the more intell­ectually developed proletarians who, in their turn, introduce it into the proletarian class struggle where conditions allow that to be done’ (Kautsky and Lenin again).” (PCInt, ‘Class and Consciousness: from Theory to Political Intervention’, Prometeo, 1st Semester 1978. Our emphasis.)

This quotation sheds much light on the errors that we have emphasised in the analysis of Bordiga and Lenin.

What is the reasoning of the PCInt?

It starts from a real premise — that the dominant ideas are the ideas of the dominant class and that the proletariat is subjected to this ideology. But from the starting point of this statement they construct an almost totally sterile and rigid analysis. First error of judgement: the workers in order to accomplish the revolution must have at their disposal a scientific analysis and an ideological understanding of the same quality as that of the class enemy. Class consciousness is a ‘scientific reflection of the experiences of the class’, it is the “reflection in the domain of ideas of the antagonism between bourgeoisie and proletariat, and is thus the subjective element which permits the overcoming of this contradiction through the revolutionary destruction by the proletariat”. So class consciousness is defined in exactly the same way as ide­ology, which is also the reflection in the domain of ideas of an objective reality (cf. Marx; The German Ideology.)

Second error of judgement: in so far as the workers submit to the dominant ideology, in so far as they are dispossessed of the means of production, they are also dispossessed of class consciousness, i.e., of the revolutionary ideology. Only revo­lutionaries, who, as members of the bourgeoisie, have at their disposal the means of intellectual production, can bring soc­ialist consciousness to the workers. So we arrive at the following absurdity: the communist revolution is possible thanks to the use of the scientific capacities of the bourgeoisie (in the service of the workers). Class consciousness becomes an ideology, in competition with bourgeois ideology, but forged with the same tools!

By trying to appear dialectical, the PCInt ends up becoming contradictory, because they tangle themselves up in their own explanations. In fact, if class consciousness is simply an ideological reflection, on what economic power does it rest? If the workers are effectively dispossessed of all economic power, how can they create an ideology? Does the ideology forged by revolutionaries float in the heavens, does it stand both inside the class struggle and within bourgeois ideology? Since the workers will always be dispossessed of the intell­ectual and material means of production, how can they accomplish the communist revolution and transform the whole of society? If their simple “class instinct” is enough, why have they not already made the revolution? By what miraculous means will rev­olutionaries manage to introduce into the class something of which the workers will always be dispossessed?

The responses of the PCInt to these questions seem very unsat­isfactory to us; they leave us hungry:

“Here resides the false problem: does socialist consciousness come from the class or from those who ‘know how to examine the laws of history’? It’s a false problem because it’s not posed in a dialectical manner, i.e., in a way that really makes it possible to grasp social and historical reality. Its solution in fact, resides outside the terms of the alternative and encom­passes both. Socialist consciousness is scientific reflection on the experiences of the class and on the problems it poses, developed by those who have the means to undertake this ref­lection, and who identify themselves politically with the class.” (Op. cit.)

No, comrades, the question we posed was not a false problem, easy to evade. The question that we posed is at the heart of two radically different conceptions of class consciousness. In failing to respond to the question “who holds and develops class consciousness?” you place yourselves in an impasse and stay inside the contradiction. The ‘dialectical’ efforts that you make to emerge from this, resolve nothing. Our conception of class consciousness attempts on the contrary, to respond to this question and to shed some light on how the proletariat will accomplish (without the help of the bourgeoisie) the communist revolution. The proletariat is the only holder of class consciousness, precisely because it has no economic power, no means of production. The consciousness of the proletariat is characterised by an indestructible link between activity and thought.

The theoretical evolution of the proletariat does not simply come as a “reflection” of its practice, it is not simply a philosophical interpretation of the world: it is an active factor, a means for the concrete transformation of reality. Theory and practice are inseparable. Only the working class in its class struggle can synthesise these two aspects of socialist consciousness. The activity of revolutionaries is certainly a privileged moment in the global and collective activity of the proletariat, but only constitutes one of its aspects (although an indispensable one). It is surely not with the same ideological weapons that the proletariat struggles against its class enemy. The revolutionary strength of the proletariat is in fact its condition as an exploited yet revolutionary class; it is a class without any power in society, and at the same time it alone is capable of releasing humanity from all forms of exploitation and class rule. Class consciousness is characterised precisely by the fact that it is simultaneously a rigorous understanding of reality and a practical transformation of it, which is something no ideology, no ‘scientific’ understanding, can be. The revolutionary power of the proletariat rests entirely and solely on class consciousness and organisation. Robbing it of the possession of this power, placing a thousand intermediaries between its theory and its class struggle, robs it of the capacity to accomplish the communist revolution. And if the proletariat as a whole is not capable of carrying out the destruction of the old world, we may as well lay down and die, for no act of will, no pious wish can change it.

Thus, despite the many contributions made by the Italian left to the enrichment of revolutionary theory, despite the courage and obstinacy with which it managed to preserve the gains of communism, the degeneration of the CI, the weight of bourgeois ideology still lies heavily on the shoulders of today’s communist groups. The ICC does not pretend to have understood everything, it does not claim to be ‘the sole holder of class consciousness’, but at least its work of reflection is based on a precise concern: to draw out the maximum number of lessons from the Russian revolution and the reflux of the revolutionary wave in the twenties, so as to avoid falling into the old traps which snared the Bolsheviks. And one of the essential lessons which comes to us from historical experience seems to us to be: only a unified and conscious proletariat can transform society. No party, no minority can substitute itself for the proletariat in the accomplishment of this task.

The German Left

The German and Dutch left represent the other revolutionary voice that tried to free itself from the counterrevolutionary chorus sung by the CI from the beginning of the twenties.

The German left was regrouped around the KAPD, which was founded in 1919 by those left-wing elements who were excluded from the ‘official’ Communist Party, the KPD(S). The KAPD, which was admitted to the CI as a ‘sympathising party’, was mainly opposed to the International’s positions on parliament and the unions (cf. Gorter’s reply to Lenin in 1920), to its conception of the united front and its support for national liberation struggles.

The KAPD tried to establish contact with the other left groups which existed within the CI, e.g., the Belgian, Hungarian, Italian, Mexican, Bulgarian and Danish left, in order to form a coherent left opposition. This opportunity was short-lived as the KAPD was excluded from the CI in 1921.

On the question of the party, the KAPD takes credit for in­sisting quite correctly on the need to build a strong coherent party capable of putting forward a global political direction and of developing class consciousness even at the risk of remaining a minority for the time being (points 7 and 8 of the theses on the party, written in 1921 to be presented at the congress of the CI). This is very far from the ‘anarcho­-syndicalist’ conception that the Bordigists like to see in the position of the German left. In the whole of the theses on the party there is no mention made of the need for the party to take power (perhaps this is the anarchist deformation with which the Italian left reproaches the KAPD). On the contrary, emphasis is placed on the role of the councils (distinct from the party) as the instruments of the dictatorship of the proletariat.

Nevertheless, the German and Dutch left were no more able to draw all the lessons from the Russian revolution and its defeat than were the Italian, British, Hungarian or Mexican left. In no document of the KAPD or the KAI (the new International created in 1922 by elements from the KAPD), is there any mention made of the fact that the substitution of the party and the state for the power of the councils had a strong effect on the degeneration of the Russian revolution.

On the contrary, several serious confusions developed within the German left.

1. Because of an incorrect analysis of the Russian revolution as both a bourgeois and a proletarian revolution (1921), and then as a bourgeois revolution, a tendency developed within the KAPD which saw the existence of a political party as the reason for the bourgeois nature of the Russian revolution.

2. By theorising the correct refusal to consider itself as a parliamentary party that should take power, a tendency was formed within the KAPD—AAUD around clearly ‘anti-party’ positions. This ‘anti—intellectual’ current was found in the Essen tendency of the KAPD, and then in the League of Council Communists. But the most well-known split with the KAPD—AAUD, at the beginning of the twenties, was the one which formed the AAUD(E) around Otto Ruble.

3. As it rejected the separate existence of a political party as such, the AAUD(E) advocated the development of organisations that were half way between the party and the coun­cils: the General Workers Union (AAU). Pursuing this analysis to its final conclusions, some elements ended up by splitting and by disbanding themselves on the basis of an anti—organisational analysis. In 1925, Ruhle himself was to give up all organised political activity.

From the beginning of the thirties, all that remained of the German and Dutch left were some elements regrouped in the SDP, isolated ‘anti—party’ individuals, terrorists like Van der Lubbe and those communist groups which came out of the AAUD(E) and denied the need for a revolutionary organisation of the proletariat to preserve the principles of the communist programme.

In fact, the big mistake of these elements of the German left (which was severely hit by the general retreat in the con­sciousness of the proletariat and by the weakness of revolution­aries in Germany during the revolutionary wave), lay firstly in their failure to understand the change in the nature and the function of the party in the decadent period. The KAPD glimpsed this change. It pointed out quite correctly the differences between the revolutionary period and the period of parliamentarism. It made a distinction between the role of the parliamentary workers’ parties of the 19th century and that of the communist party in the epoch of social revolutions. But not all of the implications of this difference were com­pletely assimilated by the German left. This is why a tendency developed within the KAPD that confused the very notion of the party with that of a mass parliamentary party. This tendency, being unable to draw out all the practical consequences of the change in period, unable to expose the substitutionist mistakes of the Bolsheviks, simply ending up by ‘throwing the baby out with the bath water’. The reasoning behind this was the following: “because the role of a party as such can only be as a leader, a parliamentary boss which tries to dominate the masses and wield power in their place, and because we re­ject this role, we will go beyond all parties.”

On the other hand, the German left always suffered from the general immaturity of the proletariat in Germany, and from the inability of revolutionaries in this country to forge a rev­olutionary party, armed with theory and ready to face the wave of proletarian struggles. For a long time the elements of the left of the SPD had hesitated to break openly with Social Democracy and form an independent party. For this reason, the KAPD appeared as a young organisation with little experience.

This general immaturity of the class played a large part in obscuring the sight of the German left, especially on the nature of the balance of forces between the classes and on the impact of the revolutionary wave. In this way the KAPD failed to see that the events of 1921 heralded the beginning of the prolet­ariat’s defeat. On the contrary, they saw it as the symbol of the height of the revolutionary movement. This over­estimation led them, in spite of themselves, into the voluntaristic adventure of the ‘March Action’ in 1921.

The numerous hesitations of the German revolutionaries, their lack of confidence in their role, the bitter setbacks undergone after the failure of the March Action, the degeneration of the CI and the reflux of the revolutionary wave, the failure to understand the change in the balance of forces between the pro­letariat and the bourgeoisie: all these things could only enc­ourage demoralisation, pessimism, and the final collapse of the German left, to the point where it ended up resorting desperately to terrorist action. Contrary to the Italian left who were able to draw up a more realistic balance sheet of the period, the German left showed itself to be weak and unable to understand what would be the responsibilities of revolutionaries during the counter—revolution. Unlike their Italian comrades, the German revolutionaries did not form themselves into a fra­ction capable of defending tooth and nail the gains of the past struggles.

This is why, today, far from maintaining and expressing a clear and coherent continuity with the past revolutionary wave, far from expressing the strength of the German and Dutch left in their critique of the CI, the present—day councilist organisations are an extreme manifestation of all its weaknesses and confusions.

Just like the Bordigists, the councilists too deny the potent­ially revolutionary nature of the economic actions of the class. Their analysis of the revolutionary process, like that of the groups of the Italian left, ends up by snatching from the pro­letariat the possibility and the necessity of going beyond a ‘trade unionist’ level of struggles and consciousness. Although for the Bordigists this inability is made up for by the existence of the party, for the councilists, as for the anarcho-syndicalists, it is the economic struggle by itself that suffices to destroy the state. For Daad en Gedachte, a fairly sclerotic example of the Dutch left, there is no qualitative difference between a strike contained by the unions and the communist revolution. This group pushes an apology for the economic struggle to the point of absurdity and ends up with the clearly ‘economistic’ positions of the 2nd International and of Lenin. But unlike Lenin, who in spite of everything saw the need for the proletariat to go beyond a trade union level, Daad en Gedachte does not cease to eulogise about the economic struggle. The qualitative extension of the struggle is suffic­ient to shake the old world. And for Daad en Gedachte it is out of the question that this quantitative accumulation can also transform itself into a qualitative development:

“The revolution doesn’t differ essentially from these daily class actions, for example by the fact that the workers raise themselves to a higher level of consciousness during the course of the revolution. The revolution does not at all differ qualitatively from these class actions, the only difference is a quantitative one.” (Daad en Gedachte, May 1975.)

For Daad en Gedachte, the consciousness of the working class is purely empirical and immediate. The workers don’t need to generalise their organisational and political experiences. Each struggle is sufficient in itself, contained in its factory, in its region, within its limited territory. The councilists don’t understand at all the revolutionary character of economic struggles and the need for their political extension through the homogenisation of class consciousness. Here we find an old refrain dear to Social Democracy: the movement is every­thing, the end is nothing!

It is logical that this immediatist conception of class con­sciousness leads the councilists to topple into unionism and localism and to completely neglect the role of revolutionaries within the struggle. In certain cases this underestimation leads to a pure and simple negation of any role for revolution­aries at all. In this way Daad en Gedachte stay with the limits of an activity that is strictly theoretical and academic. But pushed to its final conclusion, the councilists’ apology for the strictly economic struggle of the proletariat ends in the pure and simple self-destruction of all revolutionary organisation.

The councilists are no more capable than are the Bordigists of reaping the political fruits left by the ripening of the revolutionary wave in the twenties. They are no more capable of separating the wheat from the chaff, of safeguarding the need for a political organisation of the proletariat while rejecting substitutionist aberrations. The councilists like the Bordigists are the price paid for fifty years of counter­revolution, fifty years of confusion and theoretical bewild­erment, during which time the revolutionaries who succeeded in swimming against the current were few and far between. Only a group like the Gauche Communiste de France (which published the review Internationalisme in the 1940’s and 50’s) showed themselves capable of preserving the precious gains bequeathed by the experience of the Russian revolution. As is shown by one of Internationalisme’s texts, ‘On the nature and function of the political party of the proletariat’, published in October 1948, this group was almost the only one that did not fall into the political deformations which are revealed both in the positions of the Bordigists and those of the councilists.

False theories of the party - Conclusion

  • 1903 reads

We can conclude very simply by repeating that the confusions of the Bordigists and those of the councilists have the same origins: the failure to understand the revolutionary character of defensive struggles. These two political currents, which are apparently so different, come together in their confusions. Because any political position which rests on a separation between economic and political struggles implies the negation of the proletariat as a revolutionary class capable of becoming conscious of its historic aims. This is where Bordigism and councilism lead.

To insist upon the proletariat’s inability to go beyond the strictly defensive terrain by its own strength, to repeat that it is up to the party to fill the gap, this is basically to affirm that it is not necessary for the proletariat to go beyond this terrain. The modernists drive the nail in even further by pretending that when the working class struggles for economic demands it is a ‘c1ass-for-capital’, that is, an economic category completely subject to capitalist domination. It is not surprising that such a view of consciousness has pushed the majority of modernists into the arms of petit-bourgeois despair.

Both the Bordigists and the councilists separate class consciousness from the objective conditions which enable the struggle to develop. Both look upon revolutionaries as elements exterior to the proletariat. For the former, consciousness cannot by developed by the proletariat itself; it is therefore a matter of importing their consciousness from outside, and it is the party that performs this function. For the councilists the role of revolutionaries must be limited to a philosophical one, simply as intellectual spectators; this immediately places them outside the concrete struggles of the class. Neither of them understand that a correct and dialectical conception of class consciousness and its flowering goes hand in hand with an understanding of revolutionaries as a living and active part of their class.


Source URL:https://en.internationalism.org/pamphlets/cconc/3_false_theories